THE LOGIC OF NAMES. THE LOGIC OF NAMES. AN INTBODUCTION BOOLE'S LAWS OF THOUGHT. I. P. HUGHLINGS. " The symbolic language of Algebra, framed wholly on notions of number and quantity, is adequate, by what is certainly not an accident, to the representation of all the laws of thought."— DE MORGAN. LONDON : JAMES WALTON, 137, GOWER STREET. 1869. LONDON I PRINTED BY WEKTHEIMER, LEA AND CO., FI5JSBURY CIRCUS. CONTENTS. PAQE. INTRODUCTION >. 1 i. Logic . . . . . ' i . ' . . 3 n. Mind 4 in. Thought 5 IT. Nervous Action ,, v. Naming 8 vi. Sensations 11 vn. Compound Sensations ...... 12 vin. Abstraction 20 ix. Consciousness 26 x. Grammar 28 xi. "Words. ........ „ xii. Names ... . - 39 xin. Meaning . . . . • . . . 42 xiv. Relation . . . . . . . . 45 xv. Propositions . " . . . . . . 46 xvi. The Copula 47 xvn. Terms . . . 48 xvni. Logical Wholes . 49 xix. Logical Equality 53 xx. Numerical Values '. 54 xxi. Classification ........ 58 xxn. Logical Addition 71 xxni. Logical Subtraction 72 xxrv. Predication . . " . . . . 74 xxv. Predicables . . . . . . 77 xxvi. Logical Multiplication ...... 78 xxvii. Negative Propositions . . .... . 80 xxvui. Calculus of Logic . . . . . 82 2017249 ADVERTISEMENT. PRIMARILY these pages are an attempt to inde- pendently think out and popularly interpret some of the principles characteristic of Mr. John Stuart Mill's Logic, of the late Professor Boole's Laws of Thought, and of Mr. De Mor- gan's various publications on the same class of subjects. The following special objects have been aimed at: — 1st. To, so far as possible, divest of their mathematical dress the foundations of Professor Boole's theory. 2nd. To independently and popularly expound and interpret these foundations. 3rd. To include in this exposition some ac- count of certain phrases and doctrines which have been taken and adopted from the logic of the past by common language and general literature. I. P. H. THE LOGIC OF NAMES. INTRODUCTION. — Man is a result of the opera- tion of forces, some of which are known, and some unknown ; the former subjects of know- ledge, the latter subjects of belief. To the unknown we give the name of Soul ; those that are known we refer either to Mind or to Body. By the distinction of Mind and Body is not necessarily implied that between material and immaterial. The immaterial we refer to the unknown, to what is subject of belief ; but the mate- rial each man divides for himself into that which he cannot separate from his own individuality, and that which he can so separate. Such a dis- tinction is manifestly both ambiguous and fluctu- ating. It is ambiguous, because it may be under- stood in two senses. We may draw the dividing line through different systems of points. It is fluctuating, because, wherever placed in the first instance, no subsequent tracing will repeat it. The line may be drawn so as to separate all the matter which composes the individual's body from other matter. Such a line is uncertain to the kitten, which runs after its own tail, and to the human 2 THE LOGIC OF NAMES. being who, applying crossed fingers to the tip of his nose, imagines for an infinitesimal portion of time that he has two noses. A cultivated man attempts to draw the line so as to include the thinking part of his material frame only. Or, rather, he assumes the line to be drawn, and calls all on one side Mind, all on the other Bod}'. When he sees a case of conscious insanity, a madman who knows he is mad, his line fades away from even his imagination. The distinction between Mind and Body now to be insisted on is this, — that the former is con- nected with Soul, and so connected as not in our thoughts to be either separable from it or coni- binable with it, while in our knowledge it is both. Mind is mutable and destructible by material agencies, Soul is not. Mind is materially mani- festible, Soul is not. "VVe ourselves are the two together ; yet how can the material act with the immaterial ? But if Mind is that part of matter, or is in- volved indissolubly with that part of matter which a man in thought is forced to segregate into his own individuality, — if it is that part of matter which enters into the constitution of the man, what is shown to us of it is a very small portion either of Mind or Man. We can only see so much of it as is revealed in the mirror of lan- guage ; and that much, while not all its length and breadth, is none of its depth. The province of Logic, however, is, in all directions, determined by the scope of language. Logic, accepting the limitation so prescribed, is careful, in defining the field of its speculations, not to pronounce any opinion on what may lie outside the area thus set apart. I. LOGIC. — Logic is the name of the science, or art, or instrument, in obedience to which, or by means of which, we analyse verbal representations of mental affections. As a science, logic pro- fesses to give an account of the laws which words necessarily obey when they are used in exhibiting processes of thought. As an art or instrument, it furnishes, or is used to furnish, rules by which thinkers may be guided to the correction of in- accuracies of thought or expression. A book which gives an account of logic is called a Logic.* * Compare De Morgan's Syllabus of Logic, Section 1st. Logic has also been defined " as the science of the conditions on which correct thoughts depend, and the art of attaining to correct, and avoiding incorrect, thoughts " ; and as " the art of thinking, which means of correct thinking, and the science of the conditions of correct thinking." Sir William Hamilton defines logic as " the science of the laws of thought as thought." His remarks on the terms of this definition may be summarised as follows : — 1st. Logic is from the Greek adjective XoyiKjj, itself from Xoyog, a substantive which meant, sometimes, "thought," sometimes, " the expression of thought." It was equivalent both to the ratio and to the oratio of the Latins. 2nd. Logic is a science, because it is a branch of knowledge. The distinction between logic as a science, and logic as an art, at best only amounts to saying that it can be viewed in more than one way ; that it is a science when viewed absolutely, and not in relation to practice ; an art when viewed as the application to practice of knowledge. Even this distinction, however, which distinguishes nothing, is 4 THE LOGIC OF NAMES. II. MIND. — "What we know in ourselves we have received from without, from what we call Body ; and that in us which receives we call Mind. The medium of communication between body and mind is furnished by the nerves. The nerves discharge this function by successive acts which, in their affection of the mind, are called sensa- tions. The science of Mind is Psychology.* Logic is the science of Mind, only in so far as it regards mind when verbally manifested. arrived at only by help of a wrong distinction of arts and sciences. Art is a productive habit, poetic, or poietic as the Greeks said, and is opposed to a habit merely of action, to a practical habit, in the Greek sense of the word whence we derive practical. Thus, ethics is a science with a practical side, but that does not make it an art as well as a science. 3rd. Thought consists of the acts of the faculty of comparison. In this sense, thought is a recognition of similarity or difference between the objects which are submitted to the faculty of comparison by its subsidiary faculties. Logic, however, has only to do with the kind or manner of this recognition ; that is to say, with this recognition as recognition. Hence, by " thought as thought" is meant the kind or manner of thought, in technical language the Forms of thought, or Formal thought. Again, the form of thought, as the object matter of a science, may be either contingent or necessary ; that is to say, either such a form as may or may not appear, or such as must appear. Logic has only to do with the form of thought that must appear, that is, with necessary forms of thought. But the necessary forms of thought must be those which are deter- mined by the nature of the thinking subject itself, which there- fore are not acquired but original, which therefore are universally operative, and, consequently, are the laws or conditions of thought. * Psychology has been described to be the Phenomenology of Mind ; to treat of certain phenomena called mental, which are con- ceived to establish the existence and describe the nature of an im- material mind. It seems hard to distinguish it as a real science from that portion of physiology which treats of man's nervous system. THOUGHT — NERVOUS ACTION. 5 III. THOUGHT. — Mental affections* capable of being expressed by words, or other signs, or which are actually thus expressed to the conscious- ness of the individual affected, are thought.f IY. NERVOUS ACTION .J — It has been said that what we know conies from without to the mind, and that it comes to us by means of nervous action. In its simplest form, the nervous action of animals consists of an interchange of action between two sorts of nerves ; to one of which sorts we may, so far as our knowledge goes, refer every nerve. A nerve is either afferent or efferent. An afferent nerve, by transmission of an external force, is the cause to an animal of an internal affection ; an efferent nerve carries outward again to the ex- * Note that bodily affections are also capable of being ex- pressed by signs. f The hypothesis of the text is not intended to contradict, and does not contradict, the existence of volition. Nothing but ex- periment can show that any particular phenomenon is an act of volition : many phenomena, once thought to be acts of volition, experiment has shown to be independent of volition : of very few phenomena would it be possible to say that experiment had shown them to be acts of pure volition, undetermined by aught else. J In this and the following sections, no attempt is made to introduce more of the results of physiology than is absolutely necessary to give a meaning to the word sensation. Much is nevertheless owing to Professor Huxley's "Elementary Phy- siology," to Dalton's "Human Physiology," and especially to the edition of Mr. Herbert Spencer's " Psychology," now publish- ing. The student may be particularly recommended to Draper's "Human Physiology," for some very suggestive and valuable remarks on the compatibility of physiological results with those of a non-materialistic philosophy. 6 THE LOGIC OF NAMES. ternal world what of the force brought in is not wanted to sustain the internal affection, and in this way is capable of exhibiting the internal affection. In some cases of very simple organi- sation, the efference is almost immediately sequent on, and almost exactly complementary to, the afference. In those cases, nervous action might be, not unfairly, diagrammatised by the capital letter II, the downward stroke representing the afferent nerve, the upward the efferent ; the af- ference proceeding into efference without any visible breach of continuity. The capital letter Y may represent the case next in order of com- plexity, where we find the afferent nerve merge its continuity in a nervous vesicle, or a collection of nervous vesicles, which we may call a nervous centre ; and out of which again emerges the ef- ferent nerve (or nerves). And a still more com- plex case may be represented, still diagrammati- cally, but more imperfectly, by the letter W, where three nervous centres interpose between the first afferent and the last efferent nerve, and where we may distinguish the first upstroke from the second, by saying that it stands for a centri- petal nerve ; and the second downstroke from the first, by saying that it stands for a centrifugal nerve.* But this last diagram is very inadequate, since the connection between any two nervous * So far as is known, however, the number of the efferent nerves which may be excited, is not regulated by the number of the afferent nerves which excite them. NERVOUS ACTION. 7 centres implies both centripetal and centrifugal connections. 5. The idea, then, of nervous action, is simply that of afference and efference, as the idea of a railway system is that of trains bringing things and people in, and taking things and people out. But if we look at a map of England, we observe that the railways have a many great centres of junction, independent of and yet connected with one another, at London, Birmingham, Manchester, and other places, and that at any one of these centres there are trains that stop, trains that start, and trains that pass through ; with all manner of other differences between the various trains and companies. So, in considering the phenomenon of nervous action, while we accept the words afference and efference as expressive of its idea, we shall in its details expect to meet with more than all the complications of Bradshaw. Of these details it is not necessary here to say else than this, — that there are in the human body at least three nervous centres, practically independent of one another, yet connected, and in mutual relations of superiority and inferiority. 6. The nervous centre which is most compre- hensive and elaborate in its connections and branches is that which is placed in what physio- logists call the cerebral hemispheres. This is that part of the body which man is wont to asso- ciate with his individuality, and material injury or benefit to which he calls injury or benefit to his mind. And this is that part of the nervous 8 THE LOGIC OF NAMES. system in which structural complexity and ob- scurity is at its highest, and where nervous action can only be imagined by aid of the analogies afforded by less complex and less obscure nervous systems.* V. NAMING. — The result of efferent nervous action which proceeds from excitements of the simpler nerve centres is muscular action of va- rious degree and kind.f In the case of the * In the five-rayed star-fish, we have a separate nervous centre, or ganglion, for each limb, and its nervous system might be diagrammatised by five letters V, all with their angles in the circumference of the same circle, but with their limbs outside the circle. Each ray of the fish must be supposed to contain one letter. This, we are told, is perhaps the simplest form of nervous system extant as an independent existence. f Here I must note some facts which may be contradictory of the hypothesis of the text, and which I owe to Dr. Hughlings Jackson, whose special writings on the subject are named in another note. While all language is placed by the text on the same level, it appears that disease of a particular part of the brain may induce partial or complete defect of what is intelligibly distinguished by Dr. Hughlings Jackson as intellectual language, and not cause corresponding defect of emotional or interjectional lan- guage. The typical patient in this disease misuses words, or cannot use words at all, to express his thoughts ; nor can he express his thoughts by writing, or by any signs sufficiently elaborate to serve instead of vocal or written words ; nor can he read books for himself. But he can smile, laugh, cry, sing, and employ rudimentary signs of gesticulation. So far as these means of communication serve, therefore, he is able to exhibit his feel- ings to those around him. He can copy writing placed before him, and, even without the aid of a copy, sign his own name. He understands what is said to him, is capable of being interested in books which are read to him, and remembers incidents of tales. Sometimes he is able to utter a word or cerebral hemispheres, the result seems to be naming. When, from whatever cause, an afferent nerve — either directly, by itself, or indirectly, by means of more or fewer centripetal and centri- fugal nerves — communicates its own excitement to the organisation of the cerebral hemispheres, the complementary efference throws a motor or- words, which he cannot vary, and which he must utter if he speak at all, no matter on what occasion. When excited, he can swear, and even use elaborate formulae of swearing (as, for ex- ample, "God bless my life,") which have come by use and wont to be of only interjectional value. But he cannot repeat such words and phrases at his own wish or the desire of others. And as he is able to copy writing, so he can, when circumstances dictate, as it were, to him, give utterance to phrases of more special applicability. Thus, a child being in danger of falling, one speechless patient, a woman, was surprised into exclaiming^ " Take care." But in this, as in every modern case, the patient remains perfectly incompetent to repeat at pleasure the phrase he has just used so appropriately and has so distinctly uttered. It would seem that the part of the brain affected in such cases, is that which is susceptible of education to language, and which has been, after the birth of the patient, so educated. The effect of the disease, in relation to speech, is to leave the patient as if he had never been educated at all to language, and had been born without the power of being so educated. The disease in question is an affection of but one side, the left side of the brain. This fact, coupled with the undoubted obser- vation that speech is an acquired faculty, has led some physio- logists to suppose that but one side of the brain is educated to speech. The left side of the brain governs the right side of the body, and hence it has been said that most people are born " left- brained," just as most people are born "right-handed." Dr. Hughlings Jackson, however, is of opinion that both sides of the brain are educated to speech, and that, in the disease under remark, the patient is speechless, but not wordless : his defect is an in- ability to reproduce voluntarily the most special of the acquired processes of speech. 10 THE LOGIC OF NAMES. ganisation into activity, which results either in language, or, if, from whatever cause, arrested before it reaches the stage of language, in some- thing which is so far an equivalent to language, as to in turn become, like language itself, a cause of afferent nervous action. This efferent motor activity, either in its more incipient stage, which is thought, or its complete phase, which is language* we will call in its simplest act, naming. Naming, therefore, is an indication or exhibition of a dis- turbance or decomposition which has been excited in the hemispherical nervous centre by the action, more or less complicated, of afferent or centripetal nerves.f * The relation here hypothetised may be taken to explain the generally admitted connection of thought with language, even in cases where no voice, or writing, and little or no imagination of words are present in sense or consciousness with thought. And, taken in connection with what is said elsewhere in the text, it may also explain how men can make and use a name long before they can give a clear account of its meaning. Thus, in Sir W. Hamilton, St. Augustine says, " If you ask of me what is Time, I know not; if you do not ask me, I know." And thus, Archbishop Thomson says, " The names we employ in speech are not always symbols to another of what is explicitly under- stood by us, but, quite as often, are symbols both to speaker and hearer, the full and exact meaning of which neither of them stop to unfold, any more than they regularly reflect that every sovereign which passes through their bands is equivalent to 240 pence ! " t One of the most recent observations of physicians is, that disease of a particular region of the left cerebral hemisphere is followed by a complete or partial loss of power in the naming process, and by consequent inability to speak, even when all the machinery of voice and articulation recognised in anatomy re- mains untouched. On this subject the reader is referred to the SENSATIONS. 11 8. The affection of the hemispherical nervous centre which is signified by a name, we may call a sensation. And as Mind, if not necessarily to be identified with that nervous centre, at least is in a connection with it, which is like that of a body of railway proprietors to a railway, and is only terminable by death (also, perhaps, by in- sanity), we may conveniently describe a sensation as a mental affection. VI. SENSATIONS.* — A sensation is a mental state induced by the action, mediate or imme- diate, of one or more afferent nerves, and signified by the consequent reflex excitement of one or more efferent nerves.f It is not necessarily a momentary affection of mind. Its duration va- ries, it would seem, according to the degree of nervous force employed in its production. By the duration of a sensation is meant the length of footnote on the first sentence of this paragraph, to Dr. Hughlings Jackson's "Physiology and Pathology of Language" (in the press ; Churchill, London,) and to the same author's papers in the "Medical Times and Gazette" for December 14, and De- cember 21, 1867. I gladly take this opportunity of acknow- ledging the assistance I have derived from the suggestions and directions which Dr. Hughlings Jackson has given me in matters of physiology. * Sensation was denned by Dugald Stewart as the " change in the state of mind which is produced by an impression upon an organ of sense, of which change we can conceive the mind to be conscious, without any knowledge of external objects." f The text, it may be observed, does not assert that every affection of every afferent nerve induces a particular mental 12 THE LOGIC OF NAMES. time for which, in any individual case, it may continue to form a part of the human organisa- tion. Sensations may be repeated or re-excited. A sensation may be repeated by a repetition of its original cause. As a tuning-fork may be set vibrating, if its own particular note, or one har- monic with it, be sounded in its neighbourhood, so a sensation may be re-excited by the repetition or the re-excitement of the sensation next after or next before it in order of time. In other words, " if any two mental states be called up together, or in succession, with due frequency and vividness, the subsequent production of one of them will suffice to call up the other, and that whether we desire it or not."* 10. Of those sensations which are distinguished by names, few are simple or elementary, though many, if not all, appear on first impression to be simple. To draw the finger along a tablet gives a sensation which might appear to be simple, but which is certainly to be resolved into the following elements : — i. A sensation of time, ii. A sensation of contact. in. A sensation of muscular action. iv. Re- excitement of former related sensa- tions, and of the relations of those sen- * From Professor Huxley. "What are called phenomena of memory, and, probably, those phenomena also which are termed acts of judgment and imagination, seem to be wholly or partially constituted by re-excitements of sensations. f From Professor Huxley. COMPOUND SENSATIONS. 13 sations, severally and collectively, to the present sensation. v. Re-excitement of sensations not formerly related in knowledge, and of their rela- tions with the present excited relation. VII. COMPOUND SENSATIONS. — The same sen- sations are so often repeated and re-excited in the same mutual adjacencies of time, as commonly to come to be regarded as forming, collectively, separate and independent existencies, of which the corporated integrity is generally the first fact recognised by the mind, and is ever after regarded as the principal fact. That is to say, the com- pound sensation is at first taken for a simple sen- sation, as the Cathedral of Glasgow was supposed by the St. Kilda islander to be a rock hollowed out. And even afterwards, when the compound nature of the collective sensation is discovered, its indi- vidual integrity is still strongly emphasised in consciousness. Men call their consciousness of its integral individuality a perception* and they * " The word Perception expresses the knowledge we obtain, by means of sensations, of the qualities of matter." DugaldSteivart apud Dean Mansel. Other definitions of perception are that " it is the apprehension through sense of external things," and that it is " an apprehension of the relations of sensations to one another," or "a discerning of the relation or relations between states of consciousness." (See Herbert Spencer's " Psychology.") The perception of an object has been called also an Intuition, so far as it is an act of the mind. Its product, in the same system of language, is a Presentation or Cognition or a Singular Representation. 14 THE LOGIC OF NAMES. suppose the several causes of its different com- posing sensations to be qualities inherent in some material existency which is independent of, but analogous to, the human individuality, and which is accordingly distinguished as a body or thing. But when again, afterwards, on further repetition of the compound sensation, they discover that it encloses another compound sensation, its kernel as it were, which is also the kernel of other similarly inclusive compound sensations, they find themselves unable to give this compound too an objective reality of the same description with that of the former. They cannot call it a body or thing, because, although, on the one hand, it re- mains still one and the same sensation, on the other hand, they find it repeated in more than one body or thing, and never find it isolated and un- compounded with other sensations. Thus, Sir William Hamilton says, " Let B, C and D repre- sent a series of individual objects which all agree in possessing the resembling attributes of y, y, y, and severally diifer, in each respectively possessing the non-resembling attributes i, o, u. * * * The qualities expressed by y, y, y, determine in us cognitive energies," cause in us such and such sensations, " which we are unable to distinguish, and which we therefore consider as the same." This fact, however, does not make men reconsider their hypothesis of the cause of the larger com- pound sensation, of the B, or C, or D. They refuse to say that they know the smaller sensa- tion, the y, in the same way that they know the COMPOUND SENSATIONS. 15 larger, the B, or 0, or D. Calling it a concept, a notion, or an idea, they deny that it has any inde- pendent and absolute existence as an object of thought at all. " It is not cognizable in itself." Its existence is only relative.* At the same time, they describe this non-cognizable non-existent, as a mental fact, internal, subjective to the man, as opposed to the body or the thing which they call a material fact, external and objective to the man. But on the hypothesis of this book, things and bodies, no less than concepts and ideas, are called mental objects, seeing that they are all alike groups of sensations, or compound sensa- tions, of each of which the component parts are mutually bound together by the one relation of adjacency of time. In space these different groups of sensations are, neither bodies nor con- cepts, mutually independent and distinct, for they all repeat, more or less identically, the same elements. Their mode of composition is not strictly analogous to that of their representatives in language. For although names repeat more or less the same letters and syllables, these letters * Sir W. Hamilton thus negatively describes it — ""We cannot figure in imagination any object adequate to the general notion or term man ; for the man to be here imagined must be neither tall nor short, neither fat nor lean, neither black nor white, neither man nor woman, neither young nor old, but all and yet none of these at once." With the exception of the italicised words, this description is a faithful account of the facts con- sidered in the text. The groups of sensations which are called by Sir W. Hamilton " concepts" are like certain chemical elements — they are never found but in combination. 16 THE LOGIC OF NAMES. and syllables are not numerically the same. The a in antelope is, numerically, one a ; the a in apple, numerically, another a. Similarly, we cannot strictly compare the grouping in com- pound sensations to the elementary composition of chemical molecules. The molecular formulae (SO4) Zn and (SO4) M2 contain the same elements, it is true, yet the atoms which are supposed to constitute the SO4 of the one molecule do not necessarily constitute the SO4 of the other. But as an astronomer, in his fancy, could arrange the stars of the sky into groups on different systems, so that it might be possible for the same star, keeping in the same place, to be at once the nose of a bear, or the tail of a lion, or the mid-blade of a sword : or, as the same astronomer may be a working member of this society, an honorary member of that, and secretary to a third; a principal man in this social circle, a respectable outsider in another ; a member of the Greek church, but a subject of the British sovereign : so one and the same sensation finds a place for itself in innumerable different groups, in each of which it occupies a different relative position, while in all it remains unchanged and the same, relatively to other sensations, in its absolute position. In the words of Sir W. Hamilton : — " We are conscious to ourselves that we can repeat our acts of consciousness, — that we can think the same thought over and over. This act, or this thought, is always in reality the same, though manifested at different times : for no one can imagine that in COMPOUND SENSATIONS. 17 the repetition of the one and the same thought, he has a plurality of thoughts ; for he is conscious that it is one and the same thought which is re- peated, so long as its contents remain identical." 12. All sensations that are really compound but apparently simple, have, on repetition or re- excitement, a tendency to resolve, to become more distinct. Their individual elements, more or fewer of them, begin to individually assert them- selves ; and the sensation which, before, was in knowledge integral, now becomes many — now be- comes a group of sensations. By repetition it is that a sensation is enabled to enter into more groups than one, and that the intricate combinations ex- hibited in language are made possible. But to the mind, as a body of sensation, language is a gar- ment which is some times scanty, and sometimes voluminous. These sensations have more than one name a-piece, those no name at all. Some- times a sensation gets so identified with a particu- lar relation, as to lose in repetition its own identity, and its name in that relation loses all absolute meaning ; in other relations it still retains an independent existence to the consciousness, and its name has again a separate meaning assigned to it, or, perhaps, is duplicated by, or abandoned for, another, possibly more significant, name. There's an ocean round our words That overflows and drowns them. * * * * Speech is hut broken light upon the depths of the unbroken. * George Eliot's " Spanish Gipsy." C 18 THE LOGIC OF NAMES. 13. The complications thus occasioned, though considerable, would not by themselves be so intri- cate as they become in result of another fact. All sensations (there might be reason for adding, and the names* of some sensations) become, for a greater or less extent of time, a physical part of the human organisation. This many of them begin to be at such an early date in life, some probably before actual birth, and continue to be to such a late date, possibly are transmitted here- ditarily to posterity, that the mind presents no record of their first reception, and small sign of its being possible for a mind to have them not. Barest skill that Pablo half had caught From an old, blind and wandering Catalan; The other half was rather heritage From treasure stored by generations past, In winding chambers of receptive sense. * * * * Shall the mere curl of eye-lashes remain, And God-enshrining symbols leave no trace Of tremors reverent ? That maiden's blood Is as unchristian as the leopard's.f 14. Such or some such mental affections are those that have been put apart from others, and called innate ideas. Nor is it wonderful, when the seeming random and fortuitous way in which sensations hit, as it were, the mind, is com- pared with the ordered mode in which the same sensations are exhibited in thought and language, * That is, not as the causes, but as the products or accompani- ments of sensations. t George Eliot & " Spanish Gipsy." COMPOUND SENSATIONS. 19 that people should be inclined to think of the mind as an active agent, and to figure to themselves that Mind deals with sensations as a builder deals with building materials. A builder takes bricks, and stones, and beams ; classifies and catalogues them as convenience may dictate ; puts them in store for use, and from, his store selects at any time what he may want for due arrangement into forms of building. • So Mind is thought to recog- nise objects by means of perception ; by means of comparison and differentiation, or, generally, of abstraction, to shape out from its perceptions con- cepts or notions ;* by means of language, to classify and catalogue the things which it has thus found and formed ; by means of memory to store them ; by means of reason to arrange them into proposi- tions and trains of argument.^ Of such imaginations this book necessarily does 110 more than take note. If all known of a kaleidoscope were this — that from without came to it, at seeming random, bits of many coloured and many shaped glass, and that these were the same bits which, with the aid of our optic organisation, we see projected in ordered, various, and infinitely numerous arrangements on the object glass, what room would not be left for * In another terminology, General Notions or Representations. f " The rude materials furnished by Sense, retained in Memory, reproduced by Reminiscence and represented in Imagination, the understanding elaborates into a higher knowledge, simply by means of Comparison and Abstraction. The primary act of Com - parison is exerted upon the individual objects of Perception and Imagination alone." — Sir W. Hamilton. 20 THE LOGIC OF NAMES. conjectures as to the nature and the action of the kaleidoscope ! But the most ignorant of civilised men has just enough knowledge to confine within limits all such conjecture : there is nothing in the kaleidoscope which he is accustomed to call life. If the kaleidoscope had life, however, should we then consider him justified in framing a Mela- physic of kaleidoscope ? Perhaps we might. But the explanation which the optician now gives of the kaleidoscope would remain unmodified by any admission, if any admission were made, that the kaleidoscope was alive. And so whatever hypo- thesis may be entertained of the agents which produce what are called perceptions and concepts, it remains that, so far as our knowledge goes, the elementary constituents of both are alike, and are bound up by a like relation. The same elements enter by turns into the composition of a sensation, of a perception, of a concept, and of a judgment or proposition, and are in each case united by the same mode of connection. VIII. ABSTRACTION.* — Among those already * Archbishop Thomson describes Abstraction as a process of five acts : — " 1. Comparison is the act of putting together two or more single objects, with a view to ascertain how far they resemble each other. 2. Reflection is ascertainment of their points of resemblance and their points of difference. 3. Abstraction is the separation of the points of agreement from those of difference, that they may constitute a new nature, different from, yet including, the single objects. 4. Generalisation [without which, the Archbishop elsewhere says, there can be no abstraction] is the recognition of a class of things, each of which is found to possess the abstracted ABSTRACTION. 21 mentioned, it is an important note of sensations that the same simple or compound sensation has the power of being a member of an indefinite number of different groups of sensations. The differences between compound sensations that, in this way, contain a majority of common elements, appear, in mind, only as results of the repetition or re-excitement of the several compound sensa- tions, and of their consequent resolution into parts. A man, who is neither a huntsman nor a shepherd, sees a flock of sheep or a pack of hounds, and, if the animals are all of the same size and shape, knows not, else than numerically, one from the other. The shepherd or huntsman probably distinguishes each individual animal in the flock or pack from all the rest,* and possibly has a distinct name for every one of them. The reason is, that each animal of the flock or pack is represented in the mind by a group of sensations marks. 5. Denomination is the imposition of a name that shall serve to recall equally the Genus, or Class, and the Common Nature." * " The Laplander by long practice knows and gives a name to each rein-deer, though, as Linnaeus remarks, ' to distinguish one from another among such multitudes was beyond my comprehen- sion, for they were like ants on an ant-hill.' In Germany, shepherds have won wagers by recognising each sheep in a flock of a hundred, which they had never seen till the previous fort- night. * * Verlot mentions a gardene'r who could distinguish 150 kinds of camellia, when not in flower; and it has been positively asserted, that the famous old Dutch florist, Voorhelm, who kept above 1,200 varieties of the hyacinth, was hardly ever deceived in knowing each variety by the bulb alone." — Darwin's "Animals and Plants under Domestication." 22 THE LOGIC OF NAMES. which, while it contains very many elements that are common to the groups which represent its fellows, also includes comparatively a few elements that are proper to itself: the group representing the individual animal constituting in common language a perception, and that which comprises only the elements common to all the individuals forming a concept. The constituent elements, however, whether of the perception or concept, do not appear but in result of many repetitions. The shepherd or huntsman has had the advantage of such repetitions, the stranger not. 16. It generally follows, therefore, that, in the case of all compound sensations which possess many common elements, the first result of repeti- tion or re-excitement is the appearance of the resemblances between the compound sensations re- peated or re-excited. The appearance of the differences between them will be a second result. In other words, men begin by seeing resemblances. Afterwards, they distinguish differences. Simi- larly, when we say that one thing or group of sensations is equal to another, we shall mean that more or fewer of the elements composing the one group also enter into the composition of the other group, and are, in our particular point of view, the characteristic element or elements of both groups. To 'say "this is like that" implies a lesser but a still remarkable elementary com- munity. But to say "this is identical with that " can obviously only mean that this name is the name for which that is a name. A sensation re- ABSTRACTION. 23 mains the same sensation, no matter how often it be repeated or re-excited. It is unaltered by being added to itself, or by being multiplied into itself. And whatever is done with it, it will still remain as it was, and where it was, and distinct from every other sensation. 17. Let us now suppose a man to have seen but one large quadruped, say a dog, and to have given it the name, Bog. This name will be to the man the name of a sensation, which he may know to be compound, but which he will certainly have very imperfectly analysed. For, show him a sheep, and he will call that a dog too. The word Dog, from a proper name, as grammarians would say, proper to one thing, will have become a common name, common to more things than one. If, now, an antelope and a goat are successively introduced, they will be " dogs " also ; but, almost simultaneously, differences between "dogs" will also have been noticed. Every time the sensation of dog number one, dog number two, dog number three, or dog number four is repeated, it resolves into more elements than it seemed to contain before. While some of these elements are re- peated in the remaining compounds, others of them are not, and seek for names of their own. Thus, one animal may get the name of "the barking dog " ; another that of " the woolly dog " ; the third may be styled " the horned dog " ; the fourth, " the horned dog with a beard." The original word, dog, will remain as the constant element or elements repeated in 24 THE LOGIC OF NAMES. all.* It is called a class name, or an abstract name, the name of a concept, a notion, or idea, of a crea- tion of the mind. The other names, so long as they remain singular — remain the names of individual animals — are called, in opposition, names of per- ceptions ; of, that is to say, things external to us, but perceived by our minds to exist, and to have qualities- which we may separately name. But the analysis we have been making in this paragraph does not suggest any such distinction. It suggests, on the contrary, that the supposition of the ab- solute existence even of this dog, or of that dog, is only a way of numerically stating the groups into which our sensations resolve themselves. This same inference is, at the same time, decisively negatived by the fact that we have no power to give any such objective reality to the contained group of elements which is common to all the dogs, although we have just as much reason for giving it to this group as we have for giving it to the group which represents any one dog. 18. The mental affections we have just been tracing involve what is called, in the literature of logic, Abstraction.^ This name supposes that in * Brown quotes from Captain Cook's account of a visit to one of the South Sea Islands:— " The inhabitants were afraid to come near our cows and horses, nor did they form the least con- ception of their nature. But the sheep and goats did not surpass the limits of their ideas, for they gave us to understand that they knew them to be birds." These same people, it appears, were already acquainted with hogs and dogs. f Professor 3 fax 3IiilZe>-'s summation of the philological his- tory of abstraction is, that all names may be derived or identified ABSTRACTION. 25 the process which has just been described the mind is really an active agent. Comparing the four dogs together, the mind finds them to agree in certain respects, and to differ in others. It throws the different qualities out of account, takes them away, abstracts them, in order to concentrate its attention on those that agree. These it brings, in thought, together, forming a concept, or a general, or an abstract idea. 19. Another view * of the same mental process is more coincident with that which it is here attempted to unfold. A vast number of objects are constantly presenting themselves to our senses ; with roots which invariably signify a general, not an indi- vidual idea, originally expressing " one out of the many attributes of a thing ; and that attribute, whether it be a quality or an action, is necessarily a general idea " (" Lectures on Language," Fifth Edition, 1866). That is, in the language of the text, the first names were names of simple sensations ; a compound sen- sation was designated by the name of the principal or the primarily recognised simple sensation among those which formed its parts. Thus Professor Max Mailer's views may be quoted in support of the hypothesis of the logic of names. He goes on to say — " The word thus formed was intended for one object only, though, of course, it was almost immediately extended to the whole class to which this object seemed to belong." This position, and the hypothesis of the text, are copiously illus- trated by Professor Max Miiller. He tells us that " moon " means to measure ; " sun," to beget ; " earth," to plough ; pasu, orpecus, to feed. "Rhine" means to run; Gangd, to go ;'' Indus," to irrigate ; "name," to know. Compare also Sir W. Hamilton's dictum, " Our knowledge commences with the confused and complex, which, as regarded in one point of view or in another, may easily be mistaken for the individual, or for the general." * From Morell, who gives it as a view of "several of the modern German psychologists." 26 THE LOGIC OF NAMES. the perception of these objects leaves mental im- pressions which continue to exist, though apart from consciousness, and which may at any time be re-awakened. "These latent impressions insen- sibly blend together by the law of similarity ; and when a result is obtained, in which all refer- ence to time and place is lost, and all memory of the actual objects of perception from which the generalisation takes place, we term this result a concept. Thus the concept, rose, it would be said, is obtained by the insensible blending of all our experiences of this flower, so soon as the varieties are all lost sight of, and the common similarity becomes absolutely predominant." IX. CONSCIOUSNESS. — A sensation, it is said, is not necessarily present to the mind. The mind must be conscious of it, advert to it, attend to it, perceive it, before it can become a mental fact, before it can have a name. Sensation may, in some cases, be almost amounting to a pain when the mind is only beginning to take cognisance of it. And of the relation which so connects a number of different sensations that they form one compound sensation, or so connects a number of compound sensations that they in turn constitute as constituent elements one great compound sen- sation, still more complex than themselves, — of that relation it may be said that it is no sensation at all. 21. In regard to these interpretations of mental phenomena, the present hypothesis is this — that CONSCIOUSNESS. 27 the intellectual mind may be viewed as a sensitive surface, the excitement of which at any one mo- ment can only take place at one point ; that this excitement may be called consciousness ; that any one particular excitement may be spoken of as a fact of consciousness (facts of consciousness thus being equivalent to what in preceding sections have been called sensations) ; that the human organisation allows facts of consciousness to be registered internally at the moment of their origin, and for a greater or lesser portion of time, remaining meanwhile latent, and not actually facts of consciousness, but still on certain con- ditions reproducible to consciousness ; and, in conclusion, that the human organisation makes possible, by signs addressed to the ear or the eye, the external registration and exhibition of facts of consciousness. The following conditions or laws of thought may be deduced from, or recon- ciled with, these hypotheses. A fact of con- sciousness must be itself, it cannot be not itself. The sign A, therefore, must be A ; it cannot be a sign which is not A. The first of these affirma- tions asserts what is called the Principle of Identity ; the second that of Contradiction, or Difference.* Again, in respect of any fact of * Differently expressed thus:— 1. It is impossible that the same quality should hoth belong and not belong to the same thing. 2. "What is contradictory is unthinkable. 3. It is im- possible that the same thing can at once be and not be. 4. The attribute cannot be contradictory of the subject. This law of Contradiction only differs from that of Identity by a negative expression. The law of Identity has been thus ex- 28 THE LOGIC OF NAMES. consciousness, A is or is not its sign. Between these two alternatives there is no mean ; and the principle which declares this fact is known as the Law of Excluded Middle.* X. GRAMMAR. — While the necessary instru- ment of thought is language, and language con- sists of words and their combinations, there happen to be many languages — that is to say, many co-ordinate and more or less equivalent systems of verbal combinations. A treatise which professes to give an account of one or more such systems will be properly called a grammar. To trace the elements of a language or languages to their historical origins, and to describe the par- ticular forms which they take, and the particular arrangements which they are susceptible of, in time and in use, is Grammar. XL WORDS, which for Grammar are many things, are for Logic only one thing, J^ames.f pressed: — 1. Everything is equal to itself. 2. In the predicate the whole is contained explicitly which in the subject is contained implicitly. 3. Xota notae est nota rei ipsius. 4. Conceptions which agree can be affirmed of the same subject at the same time. * This law has been thus expressed : — 1. Either a given pro- position or its contradictory must be true. 2. Of contradictory attributions we can only affirm one of a thing ; and if one be explicitly affirmed, the other is implicitly denied. f The distinction of parts of speech in Grammar arises from an intrusion of grammarians into) the territory of logicians, so far. that is to say, as such a distinction in speech is supposed to involve corresponding distinctions in thought. The necessary WORDS. 29 24. "When it is uttered, a name, from a result of sensation, becomes a cause, and the mind is existence of any such distinction in thought is denied by the theory of this book. Both logicians and grammarians have fetched their raw materials directly or indirectly from one and the same language, namely, Greek. From that language all the commonly — that is, the unscientifically — recognised laws of speech and thought have been virtually deduced. If any lan- guage has furnished exceptions to the laws thus made out, so much the worse for the language. It has been either dragooned into submission, or stigmatised as indulging in eccentricities beyond the pale of reason. Of this tyranny the most signal victim, per- haps, is the vernacular of England and America, where Lindley Murray and his crew of followers have been exalted into supreme authorities over the language of Shakespeare and Milton. The student will find that, within the bounds of English and Greek almost all the parts of speech are interchangeable in actual use. And within the four seas of Great Britain there is a spoken and written language which hardly recognises the distinction of case, and which places, or did place, the article, disguised to gram- marians as an expletive, before prepositions and verbs. Professor Max Miiller takes us further afield in the same sort of illustration. In his " Lecture on Language," (5th Edition, 1866), we are told that the Chinese language has, according to common report, " no grammar at all — that is to say, it has no inflections, no declension and conjugation in our sense of these words — it makes no formal distinction of the various parts of speech, noun, verb, adjective, etc. Yet there is no shade of thought which cannot be rendered in Chinese." No analysis of any kind seems to be required for the discovery of the component parts of a Chinese sentence. Thus, " the Chinese sound ta means, without any change of form, great, greatness, and to be great." That is, it is equivalent to all three English words. " If ta stands before a substantive, it has the meaning of an adjective. Thus, tajin means a great man. If ta stands after a substantive, it is a predicate. * * 1hns,jin ta (oi-jin ta ye] would mean the man is great." Again, " when we say in Latin baculo, with a stick, we say in Chinese y*c~dng. * * * This y~ is a root; it is the same word which, used as a verb, would mean " to employ." Therefore, in 30 THE LOGIC OF NAMES. affected by it as it would be by any other cause of sensation. Names thus become creatures of the voice and the hand. They have attached to them histories and prerogatives, which open themselves to the grammarian and the philologist. They serve as elementary symbols of number, and so once expressed all that men knew of mathematics. Lastly, they are symbols of sensations, and as such demand the attention of logicians. 25. Words as symbols of number have not always been distinguished from words as names. The science of number is the evolution of the con- sequences imposed upon thought by the condition of time. The most elementary of these conse- quences, being exhibitable by modifications of names, have come to be regarded as inseparable from the import of names ; and, as a necessary part, therefore, of Logic. It is a manifest con- venience of common and unscientific life to use the same word to express both a name and a number. It is as convenient to do so in elemen- tary logic as in elementary arithmetic. But as scientific arithmetic confines itself to words which are numbers only, so logic, if it also is to be scientific, must use words that are names only. In logic, therefore, " man " and " men " are, sub- ject to the exception elsewhere noted, two names for the same thing — two collective symbols for one and the same highly complex and imperfectly Chinese y All triangles contain two right angles ; ( Since ) and, because this is a triangle, this also contains two right angles ; and ii. All triangles contain two right angles ; but this s a triangle ; therefore this contains two right angles. 29. In the same spirit, Logic demands general exactness from language. Meeting with such a proposition as — All right angled parallelograms are squares or rectangles, it obliges the meaning to be made * A unwocal name is a name which has only one meaning. An equivocal name has more than one absolute and independent mean- ing. A metaphorical name is that which has more than one meaning, hut of its meanings more or fewer are temporary and provisional, in other words pronominal. Thus, a particular part of an animal is always named foot ; the lower part of a tree, or of a mountain, is sometimes named foot. WORDS. 35 independent of the matter by a more explicit statement, as — All right angled parallelograms are squares, or, if not squares, rectangles. 30. And, similarly, it paraphrases, i. All non acute angles are right or obtuse ; as, All non acute angles are right and not obtuse, or obtuse and not right. 11. The ground is wet because it has rained ; as, The cause of the ground being wet is that it has rained. And in. It has rained because the ground is wet ; as, The cause of our knowledge that it has rained is our knowledge that the ground is wet. 31. An interrogative pronoun is, in logic, simply a note of interrogation ; i.e., a name of that about which a question is asked.* The English language puts the character which marks an interrogation at the end of the sentence, but the word which marks it generally at the beginning. In Spanish, the character is put first, as well as last; in Greek, the word is often put last.t These differ- ences are only noticeable so far as they show the independence of idiomatic language, which is a characteristic of logic. 32. A proposition becomes a question by a change in the order of its words, or by a change in the incidence of its accent. Then the change of order or of accent is a logical name. * Latham. f And often in English as well. This is what ? is as idiomatic as What is this ? The first, however, illustrates better the force of an interrogative name, This is the thing about which I ask. 36 THE LOGIC OF NAMES. 33. A negative word, or affix, again, is the sign of a subtracting operation which is not performed but only indicated. In " it is not so," the sensa- tions defined by "so" are exhibited by "not" in process of subtraction from all sensations. " Not " is the name of a subtraction, which may be imaginary, and need not take place, in fact. Suppose it to have taken place, and then the form "not so" may stand for the name of the re- mainder. When it is the name, and is not standing for the name, it is no longer negative, but positive. In names like inhuman, immortal, for instance, the negative has lost its force, the subtraction by degrees having come to be regarded as having been effected, and its name as a sign 'for the remainder. 34. A pronominal word is a word which stands by convenience for another word. The list of such words in Grammar might well be extended so as to take in such words as " thus," "so," and " do," in many of their uses. In Logic, however, they are all names with provisional and temporary meanings defined by the context of the moment. If we said " swans are white," we should mean that among those elements which make up the compound sensation, "swan," is that element which we name " whiteness." It is a usage of language which imposes in certain circumstances a change of whiteness into white.* And the * Compare the word Concrete, which is a term relatively ap- plied to any one of a number of groups of sensations which contain, as a common element, another group of sensations. This common WORDS. 37 cause of this usage is another usage, — the am- biguous use of the substantive verb. "Is" or "are" may express either nominal identity or logical relation between the names it joins. In order to meet this ambiguity, language makes a change, not in that which joins, but in that which is joined. Between these two sen- tences— i. A particular compound of elementary rays is whiteness; and n. A particular compound of elementary rays is ivhite. the real difference of meaning* lies in a word that is the same in each, " is " ; which, in the first case, expresses a relation of nominal identity ; in the second, the relation which one element in a group of sensations bears to another element or elements in the same group, by virtue of their being in that one and the same group. This relation we distinguish as the logical relation. In Logic, " is " is used only in this signification. element may be abstracted from any of those -which contain it. They are concrete, therefore, and it is abstract. In this broad sense the name of any concept or notion is abstract ; that of any object, thing, or numerical individual is concrete. In a narrower but analogous sense, an abstract name may be denned as that of a quality considered apart from that which possesses it, as whiteness ; while a concrete name is that of a quality considered as being possessed by something else, as white. But this distinction is merely a paraphrase, with something like logical language, of a grammatical distinction, which answers to no difference in thought. * Supposing " white " not to be used for " whitish." 38 THE LOGIC OF NAMES. When Logic finds it to be used by common language in another signification, it can only interpret it by a paraphrase, as, for example, " James is," by " James exists." 35. If the distinction between a substantive and an adjective disappears in Logic, so does that also between a substantive and an adverb, a prepo- sition, or a conjunction. In The danger is very great, the meaning of " very " is strictly provisional to the temperament of the speaker and the cir- cumstances of the case. It means that the pro- bability of the event, or result, to which the apprehension of danger attaches, is as much nearer to 1 than to 0 as the speaker (and the hearer in assumed sympathy with him) is accus- tomed to mark, or supposes himself to mark, by the word " very." In The risk is comparatively high, " comparatively " has also a provisional meaning. Although it explicitly implies the process of com- parison, it also supposes a provisional standard of comparison. But in The bill introduced by him was avowedly directed against the neutral powers, " avowedly " has a positive signification, namely, " with an avowal that." 36. Prepositions and conjunctions in Grammar, like "is" and "do," are pronominal. Thus, "of" may stand for "belonging to," as, "the martyrs of the fight " ; for the Latin de, as in " I could not sing of love"; for "from," as in NAMES. 39 " orient hues unborrowed of the sun " ; for " by," as in " Ye shall be hated of men." * XII. NAMES. — A name f is the sign, token or * From Howard's " Grammar of the English Tongue" (pub- lished at the Education Society's press, Bombay). The imper- fections of language, so far as they are liable to affect the validity of logical forms, constitute Fallacies. A few of the instances commonly given may be noted here. " To speak of stones is possible ; to speak of stones is speech of the speechless ; therefore speech of the speechless is possible ; " •where there is an ambiguity in "of." " 7 and 2 are odd and even ; 9 is 7 and 2 ; therefore 9 is odd and even" ; where there is an ambiguity in " and. " " What he was beaten with was what you saw him beaten with ; what you saw him beaten with was your eyes ; therefore he was beaten with your eyes" ; where there is a confusion in the applications of "with." " The people suffer from famine ; you are one of the people ; therefore you suffer from famine" ; where "one of the people" is confounded with "people." " All these trees make' a thick shade ; this is one of them ; therefore it makes a thick shade" ; where the fallacy is similar to that in the preceding instance. " Projectors are unfit to be trusted ; this man has formed a pro- ject, therefore he is unfit to be trusted " ; where the conventional meaning of "projector" is taken for its etymological meaning. " What is bought in the market is eaten ; raw meat is bought in the market ; therefore raw meat is eaten " ; where the first assertion is imperfect, and might be repaired by reading, "is bought to be eaten." All such mistakes are to be guarded against, by making lan- guage state exactly that which thought presents. •(• The idea of a name, as conceived in this Logic, may be illus- trated by saying that it answers to Leibnitz's symbolical cognition, as that is defined by Archbishop Thomson, who uses the follow- ing words : — " A name, then, employed in thought, is called a symbolical cognition." 40 THE LOGIC OF NAMES. symbol of a mental idea, concept or notion ; or of a sensation, or a feeling or perception ; of some impression or impressions that have been so made on our sense, as to be felt or perceived by the mind to form one whole."* "When this sensation is simple, indivisible to the mind, its name, if it have one, is necessarily a simple name. When it is compound, is in fact not one sensation, but many, so that the mind may verbally exhibit more or fewer of these sensations ; the name may be a simple or a compound name, may, either, by a simple form, collectively designate the various simple sensations which make up the compound sensation, or by a complex form designate in detail the same compound sensation; the complex form consisting of more or fewer of the names themselves of the constituent sensations. In the former case the name may be called a simple name, in the latter a compound name ; but in each the name, as a name, is what it is in the other case. Many compound sensations have two names — one a simple name and the other a com- pound name. Ofttimes a compound sensation has no simple name, but can only be denominated, imperfectly denominated, by a name composed of the names of its parts. * Or a name may be defined as standing for a " thing," and a "thing" as " a simple or compound fact of consciousness." In what follows of the text, the words idea, concept, notion, feeling, perception, or any one of them, may be substituted, at pleasure, 1'or sensation. 4.1 These gems have life in them : their colours speak, Say what words fail of. So do many things, The scent of jasmine, and the fountain's plash, The moving shadows on the far-off hills, The slanting moonlight, and our clasping hands.* 38. Sometimes the name of one of the parts of a compound sensation stands for the whole. Some- times the parts are not distinguished, or have no name. There is, of course, no difference between simple and compound names viewed as names. f The elements of a compound name may be com- pound names themselves, and any number of words together may form but one name.J * George Eliot's " Spanish Gipsy." t " "When a language is transmitted from one generation to another, not merely the words, but their mode of connection, as sentences, is also transmitted and appropriated by unconscious imitation, and thus becomes fixed. The latter point is not suffi- ciently appreciated, though it is quite clear that we do not think in words but in whole sentences ; hence we may assert, that a living language consists of sentences, not of words. But a sentence is formed not of single independent words, but of words which refer to each other in a particular manner, like the corresponding thought which does not consist of single independent ideas but of such as, connected, form a whole, and which determine each other mutually."— Waitz, translated by Collingivood. % This seems to be the place for noticing the fact that logicians sometimes take the trouble of dividing into classes those things which it appears to them are capable of being named. Thus, Mr. Mill discusses at length the following division of things : — I. Feelings or states of consciousness. 1st. Sensations. 2nd. Thoughts. 3rd. Emotions. 4th. Volitions. 42 THE LOGIC OF NAMES. XIII. MEANING. — The " meaning " of a name is the thing or things for which it stands. Any word which has a meaning, therefore, when it stands by itself, and any " sign " whatever, is, for the purposes of this book, a name. "Even your loved words Float in the larger meaning of your voice As something dimmer."* 40. All words, then, are names ; for they may all appear in the pages of a dictionary with one or more meanings attached to them. Particles as — yes, no, to, for, by — are, accordingly, names; and we might describe a name as a sign, mark, or symbol which represents to the senses what may not be, cannot be, or is not, of itself apprehended, at the time, II. Substances. 1st. Body, or that which may he assumed to he the ex- ternal cause of sensation. 2nd. Mind, or that which may he assumed to he the in- ternal cause of sensation. III. Attributes. 1st. Qualities. 2nd. Quantity. 3rd. Eelations. a. Likeness, unlikeness. b. Nearness, distance. c. Succession, concurrence, precession. d. Being greater than, equal to, less than, e. Cause, effect. /. Etc., etc. Such classes of things are known in logical literature as cate- gories, a word which literally signifies accusations, and which has been transferred to logic in the sense of predications. The doctrine of categories has always been considered extra logical. * George Eliot's " Spanish Gipsy." MEANING. 43 by the sense.* Names may thus stand for sensa- tions which are not in effect repeated or re- excited at the moment of utterance, or which have already become parts of the human organi- sation. 41. It is possible for some compounded sensations to have become so integrated, as it were, with the physical system as to lose in consciousness their compound character. In such a case the separate names of the compounded sensations will also have lost their force as symbols of distinct things. But here to the aid of the logician comes the philologist. The history of language shows that before the integrating process had set in, or before it had reached its present stage, these very same words were in use, with very definite meanings attached. 42. When the meaning of a name consists of many parts, more or fewer of which have their own names, as in the case of the simple name of a compound sensation, the names of the sensations so compounded, or the compounded sensations themselves, are called by logicians attributes. These attributes may be thought of as the marks of the group of things which is signified under that simple name of which, collectively, their * " Jump," says the shepherd to his dog, and the dog knows that this vocal articulation orders him to make a given muscular effort. The man has spoken to the dog. During the night some one opens the gate of the farmyard, and the watchdog barks ; he thus tells his master that something unusual is happening." — Pouchet, translated by Beavan. 44 THE LOGIC OF NAMES. particular names express the meaning. And col- lectively, also, these particular names constitute to logicians the connotation, the comprehension, or the intension of that simple name. 43. To set forth the meaning of a name in terms, is to define it. When thus set forth, the meaning is called a definition* As sensations in repetition or re-excitement tend to resolve themselves, the meanings of their original names are, in the course of time and discovery, liable to be ex- tended, and their definitions, therefore, being expressed in words, to become, in a sense, incom- plete. But as long as the definition is sufficient, in view of the purpose in hand, for marking off what the name defined stands for from other things, it ought to be held to be a competent definition. Thus, "Man is a rational animal," will remain a valid definition until it can be shown that some other animal is rational also. 44. When a definition is necessarily very tem- porary or provisional in its nature, it is commonly and usefully distinguished as a description. 45. Tn language and the practice of logic, it is allowable, for the employment of a word in any * Sir William Hamilton puts definition under the wider term, Declaration, and says that a declaration is called an explication when it indeterminately involves only some of the names which constitute the meaning. It is called an exposition, when it con- tains several explications. It is called a description, when it consists of names which wholly or partially suggest only, but do not express, the meaning. Finally, in cases set forth in the text, under the head of classification, he calls it a definition proper. RELATION. 45 particular chain of reasoning, to limit or even vary its meaning. Thus, for the purposes of science, it is possible to have names the meanings of which are exhaustively and exactly statable. XI Y. RELATION.* — Since no sensation can be repeated without a revival or re-excitement of the sensation or sensations proximate to it in order of time, no two sensations become facts of conscious- ness without a consciousness of their number ; that is, of their sequence, of a fresh sensation — a sensation of relation between them. This being the one universal relation (we are accustomed to speak also of relations of equivalents, likeness, etc.^, it has been taken as a sort of necessary factor to the connection of sensations, and as that which renders any two or more simple sensations capable of being related to the same group, and of being named under the same compound name. 47. As the distinction between the elements of a compound sensation thus appears to be succes- sion, that between compound sensations themselves may be taken to be an interval or break of suc- cession. This distinction is, however, a distinction of manner, not of kind, the relation between one compound sensation and its successor being in- * This seems to be the place for noticing what have been called Relative Conceptions. A relative conception cannot be thought of alone, but only in conjunction -with its necessary complement, or correlative. Such are father and son, pronominal names, respectively used for all groups of sensations which have certain common elements. 46 THE LOGIC OF NAMES. trinsically the same as that between a simple sensation and its successor ; and the foundation of the relation is evidently without the mind. Sensations come to it in a certain order ; and this order is invariably maintained in all their repe- titions and re- excitements, and constitutes what we call its knowledge.* XV. PROPOsrxiONS.t — The name of the logical relation, if expressed, has therefore the office of a copula or nexus between the names of the con- stituent elements. It asserts that the names it is * Professor Max Mutter, in his " Lectures on Language " (5th Edition, 1866), says, " How do we know things ? "We perceive things by our senses, but our senses convey to us information about single things only. But to know, is more than to feel, than to perceive — more than to remember, more than to compare. * * * We know a thing if we are able to bring it, and any part of it, under more general ideas. "We then say, not that we have a perception, but a conception, or that we have a general idea of a thing. The facts of nature are perceived by our senses ; the thought of nature, to borrow an expression of Oersted, can be conceived by our reason only." Excepting, perhaps, the expression of Oersted's, nothing in this passage seems to amount to more than a statement of the facts discussed in the text. f A proposition which must he taken for granted as self- evident is an Axiom. If not only to be taken as a fact self- evident for belief, but as a rule to be acted on, or instrument to be employed, .it is called a Postulate. If it is not self-evidently true, but only to be shown true by means of other propositions, it is called a Theorem. "When it is of a complex order and gives certain premises (data) as the conditions of action (solution), which must result in a certain conclusion (qucEstio), it is a Problem. When it is an immediate inference from another proposition, it is called a Corollary from that proposition. A proposition borrowed THE COPULA. 47 interposed between may together form one com- pound name, or be together replaced by one simple name. Such an assertion, taken along with its subject matter, is what is called a propo- sition. In accordance with this view, a proposi- tion may be described as the exhibition of a compound name in analysis or synthesis.* The enunciator wishes, by stating a fact, to ascertain it for himself, or to demonstratef it for another. In the one case he may be said to construct a compound name, in the other to dissect it. XYI. THE COPULA. — In a proposition the name of the connecting relation is distinguished as the copula. In language the copula is sometimes understood, but most often is expressed by what is called a verbal inflection, or by the verb " to be " in some one of its forms, or, where the copula has to join compound names which themselves are in the form of propositions, by such a word from one science as an auxiliary to propositions in another science, is called a Lemma. "When it serves as an illustration only to propositions of its own science, and is not a necessary link in a main chain of reasoning, it is a Scholion. A. proposition which is proposed for discussion or proof, is termed a Thesis. "When, to explain certain facts, it is provisionally adopted as a demonstrable Theorem, it becomes a Hypothesis. * Compare Sir William Hamilton. "A concept is a judgment * not explicitly developed in thought, and not formally expressed in terms ;" "concept" answering to the "compound name," and "judgment" to the "proposition," of the text. t A demonstration is the verbal exhibition of a mental affec- tion. 48 THE LOGIC OF NAMES. as "therefore." The word "to be," however, forms the general sign of the copula ; and, as a copula, has somewhat arbitrarily ascribed to it various significations.* It can always be substi- tuted for the other signs of the copula.f XYII. TERMS.J — In a proposition, the names of the sensations between which the asserted rela- tion is supposed to exist, are distinguished as the terms. These, in the typical form of propositions, must be two in number. For, as has been already intimated, more than one sensation cannot be ex- hibited by the mind without the exhibition of a logical relation. The mind can exhibit a plurality of sensations only in the form of a succession of names coming in pairs ; the latter member of each pair being the name of the logical relation, and also the first member of the succeeding pair. The name of the logical relation, consequently, virtually becomes, in each case, a copula between the two extremes of a dipodium ; as thus — a c, c b \ b c, c d \ dc, c e \ etc.§ Such a succession * Namely, identity, accompaniment, sequence, cause, or re- semblance. t For " John runs," may be substituted "John is running." In the case of " therefore," the subslitxition would be less idiom- atic sometimes, but equally intelligible. J Terms are so called because they are considered to be the bounds or extremes of a proposition. § The dual nature of the proposition may perhaps receive a kind of illustration from the following newspaper cutting : — " He never could learn the whole lesson. In this instance he was unable to remember the third component part of gunpowder. LOGICAL WHOLES. 49 as the above is, in language, speedily transformed in to a succession of triads; thus, acb \ bed \ dee \ etc., in which each triad is a type of the ordinary proposition of language, with its two terms united by a copula.* XVIII. LOGICAL WHOLES.J — Sensations which Whichever two he remembered, the third was always forgotten. His captain, attributing this failing to obstinacy, reported the matter to the colonel, who examined the man himself. ' What is gunpowder made of ? ' — ' Charcoal, saltpetre, and — ' ' Sulphur,' said the colonel. ' Now rsmember that, my friend— sulphur. Now tell ma what is gunpowder made of ? ' — ' Sulphur, charcoal, and—' ' Saltpetre,' added the colonel. ' Now, my friend, don't be nervous ; forget that I am your colonel ; think of me only as your comrade, who, slapping you on the back, asks, Tell me, old fellow, what is gunpowder made of? What would you say ?' — ' I would say,' growled out the soldier, ' that as you know it better than I do you are a damned fool to ask me.' " * The theory involved in the text may be exemplified by stating that in the proposition " Man is mortal," it considers two judgments to be involved, having one common term, " is." "With respect to the ordinary logical distinctions between terms, as, for instance, into singular, common, collective, abstract, and attribu- tive, they are generally accounted for in subsequent paragraphs of the text. A collective noun is that which is otherwise called a noun of multitude, and is the noun of a logical whole which has been formed by a process of numerical addition. It is some- times opposed to a Distributive name which is the name of a logical whole formed by abstraction. An abstract term is the name of a quality, considered independently of that which possesses it ; as, " goodness ": an attributive term is the name of a quality considered as inherent in that which possesses it ; as. " it is good" This distinction is grammatical, like that between univo- cal, equivocal and metaphorical terms. f " Wholes may be first divided into two genera, — into a Whole by itself (Mum per se), and a Whole by accident (totum per aceidens). A Whole per se is that which the parts of their proper 50 THE LOGIC OF ^AMES. by force of a mutual relation form one group, so as to be capable of designation under one name, and which can be expressed in this connection by a compound name, by a proposition, or by a series of propositions of which their names constitute the terms, are said to form a logical whole. If, then, simple sensations in logic are taken as analogous to atoms in Chemistry, a logical whole, in its simplest form, will be analogous to a chemi- cal molecule. One definition of a name might nature necessarily constitute ; thus, body and soul constitute the man. A Whole per accidens is that which the parts make up contingently; as, when man is considered as made up of the poor and the rich. A Whole per se may, again, he subdivided into five kinds, — into a Logical, a Metaphysical, a Physical, a Mathematical, and a Collective. 1. A Logical, styled also a Universal ; a Subject or Subjective ; a Potential Whole, is a genus containing under it species, or a species containing under it indi- viduals ; and 2. A Metaphysical, styled also a Formal or an Actual Whole, is an individual as containing in it species or a species as containing in it genera. 3. A Physical, or, as it is likewise called, an Essential Whole, is that which consists of matter and of form, in other words, of substance and of acci- dent, as its essential parts. 4. A Mathematical, called likewise a Quantitative, an Integial, more properly an Integrate, Whole (totwn integratuni), is that which is composed of integral, or, more properly, of integrant, parts (paries integrantes*). In this Whole every part lies out of every other part ; whereas, in a physical whole, the matter and form, the substance and accident, permeate and modify each other. Thus, in the integrate Whole of a human body, the head, body, and limbs, its integrant parts, are not contained in, but each lies out of, each other. 6. A Collective, styled also a whole of Aggregation, is that which has its material parts separate and accidentally thrown together ; as an army, a heap of stones, a pile of wheat, etc."— From Sir JT. Hamilton. LOGICAL WHOLES. 51 make it the sign or symbol of a logical whole, and anything to which one can give a name might be called a logical whole. 52. The different ways in which names may be used in expressing logical wholes are usefully dis- tinguished by the employment of mathematical terms. The following compound name, for ex- ample, " The-tent-royal-of-their-Emperor," ex- hibits three names, (two being compound them- selves), which are written together so as to form one name as one whole. The expression consists of a single term, of which the component parts are combined without any connecting sign, as if by the algebraic process of multiplication. The actual process may, therefore, be conveniently styled the logical process of multiplication. A further analogy between this logical process and its algebraic parallel appears in the fact, that, in both cases, the relative position of any particular symbol makes no difference to its value as a factor. The entire expression would remain unchanged in import if the fancy of the writer or the idiom of the language had placed that first which now goes third, or that second which now goes first. Another language might make "the" come after "tent," or "royal" before either, and so on. Thus Mr. Morris in his " Earthly Paradise" writes lines such as this : — " Like the gold people of antiquity ;" the equivalent form to which in prose English 52 THE LOGIC OF XAMES. would have " gold " before " antiquity," in Ice- landic " the," if used at all, after " people," and in Latin " of" after " antiquity." 53. Again in the following sentence : — The angles which one straight line makeswith another falling on one side of it are two right angles, or (if) not- two-right- angles (are together equal to} two-right- angles. Considered as one proposition and relieved of the surplusage of mere language, there are four terms and a copula. Of the four terms, one comes before the copula. Of the remaining three terms, one is separated from the other two by the intervention of "or." And the two terms left are united by the word " if," which, being only a sign of multiplication, has been treated as surplus- age. But " or" is different from " if." The latter, according to the account we have given of logical multiplication, only stands for a dead copula, represents a relation supposed to be already de- monstrated, which is sufficiently evidenced with- out it. " If," at most, is like the sign x in algebraic multiplication when it is written out, and not understood. But "or," like +, is not left to be understood. It expresses an alternative, and the terms which it separates or brings to- gether are in a very different relation from that of logical multiplication. This relation may be conveniently distinguished as that of logical addi- tion. Very frequently it may be represented by " and " ; as in Merchants are wholesale dealers and retail dealers, [which we know to mean, LOGICAL EQUALITY. 53 Merchants are wholesale dealers, or if not whole- sale dealers (then) retail dealers.^ And as in English Celts and Saxons, [where Celts and Saxons are logically added to- gether by the sign " and," the name " English " being logically multiplied into each of them.] 54. Logical addition should not be confounded with the addition of number and magnitude. Such addition is frequently expressed by " and," as in " two and two are four," " water is oxygen and hydrogen," or " it is brandy and water." This ambiguity of the word " and " in part arises from that general parallelism of the sciences of names and numbers which, we shall see further on, has occasioned confusion between Classification and Logic. XIX. LOGICAL EQUALITY. — Of the various re- lations that in language may be represented by the sign of the copula, the logic of names only takes cognisance of the universal relation which has been already defined, and which may be conveniently named logical equality. This word " equality " is in logic a different thing, but not an opposed thing, to the equality of the sciences of Number and Magnitude. In logic, one thing is equal to another,* or, rather, one name is equal to another, if it may be taken in thought with * Of course, one sensation can only be equal to another so far as they are both sensations. 54 THE LOGIC OF NAMES. that name to form, as integral parts, the same logical whole. The terms of every proposi- tion, therefore, are equal to one another, the copula is a sign of logical equality, and a propo- sition is a logical equation. 56. In the case of synonyms, it should be noted that the expression of logical equality becomes an expression of nominal identity. When we say that plumbago is black lead, we mean to say that plumbago and black lead are two names for the same thing. XX. NUMERICAL VALUES. — In English gram- mar a distinction is often made between so-called common and proper names which might be ex- tended to all names. Every name in a language may be said to fall in one or other of these two classes, — the class where every name in one sense is proper to one thing, and the class where every name in one sense is common to more than one thing. The names in the latter of these classes may reasonably be called common names ; those in the former, proper names; and that number of things which a name may happen to stand for we will nominate its numerical value. 58. Names which have different senses are capable of being in some senses common names, in other senses proper names. This is an affair of usage. Thus man in one sense is proper ; it is the name of mankind. In another sense it is common, being indifferently applicable to every individual man. Viewed as being originally a NUMERICAL VALUES. 55 common name, the idiom of the English language provides two ways of using it, in derived senses, as equivalent to a proper name. " The " being placed before man, viewed as a common name, that name is made proper to some individual man ; as, " I will kill the Man who breaks this law." * In the plural number, as Men, it again, viewed as a common name, is made equivalent to a proper name, as in " Men are mortal." And both methods may be combined, as in " I will kill the Men who break this law." It appears, therefore, that a common name may be used as equivalent to a proper name, or for a proper name, — first, by having affixed the definite article, which may be called a sign of the proper sense ; second, by being inflected in the plural number. " Horse," for another example, is never, except in the sense of " horseflesh," used as a proper name. "We do not say, " Horse is a noble animal." But "horse" can be made equivalent to a proper name. "We may say, " The horse is a noble animal," or " Horses * Other examples :— The Punjauh, The Doab, The Deccan, The Peninsula, in the English of to-day ; The Bath, The Massa- chusetts, in last century English. As a general rule, when an English name of place or person is preceded by the definite article, we may assume that the name does or did connote some- thing or other in addition to what it at present denotes. At the present day Englishmen and Americans, while they usually speak of " Hamlet " and " King Lear," as generally say, " The Medea," " The (Edipus Rex." Civilians talk and write of men-of-war as " The Arethusa," " The Bellerophon," etc. In naval writing the article is frequently omitted. The causes or explanations of these variations in usage are easily suggested by what is said in the text. 56 THE LOGIC OF NAMES. are noble animals," or " The Horses of Arabia are noble animals." When a common name is much used in a particular proper sense, the force of usage and the course of time will often render unnecessary the indication of the article. Thus, we invariably say now " Massachusetts." In last century they often said, " The Massachusetts.'1 Then " Massachusetts " was at least traditionally a common name, having meant "Blue Moun- tains " ; and it was used in a proper sense, as proper to a certain province. Hence the affixed article. Now usage has turned the common name into a proper name, and the article is unnecessary. 59. A word may be used in any one proposition according to its numerical value as limited by the context, either for all the individuals it is nor- mally common to, or for some of them. In the former case it is said to be distributed ; in the latter undistributed. In "Men are animals/' "men" is said to be distributed ; in " Some men are ani- mals," 4'men" is said to be undistributed. In both propositions " animals " is said to be undis- tributed, it obviously not standing for all the individuals it is normally common to. But, in the method of this book, " some men " is regarded as a pronominal name ; that is, as a compound name with'a provisional meaning, proper in sense and distributed in logic. No numerical value has been changed. Two terms have been mul- tiplied together, and the result is a new term. The same holds of all names which stand in NUMERICAL VALUES. 57 the relation to one another of logical factors. Similarly, the alteration of numerical value in the case of " animals " is to be regarded as a change of sense. In the one proposition, it stands for one thing, that is one numerical value ; in the other proposition, for another numerical value ; in each case its numerical value being determined by the other term. But the other term, scien- tifically considered, is in each case a proper name, though with a provisional meaning ; and its nu- merical value must, by the definition of a proper name, be either 1 or 0 : — 1, if the name of a thing supposed really to exist, or of a proposition sup- posed to be true ; — 0, if the name of a thing which is supposed not to exist, or of a proposition which is supposed not to be true. As this reasoning holds of all names, for they may all be terms of propositions, it generally follows that the only numerical values assignable by the logic of names to names are 1 and 0 ; that all names are proper, and all distributed ; and that there is no logical distinction between names as singular and plural.* Manifestly the same conclusions follow from the * Except that to a singular name a plural name stands as a compound name to a siinp'e, or as the name of an included com- pound sensation to that of its larger and including compound sensation. Thus, from Professor Max Midler, we learn that "man" in Chinese is'yin, and that "the whole," or "totality," is Mai. The two, added together, give *gin-kiai, the Chinese for "men." And again, pe'i in Chinese means "a class," i means "a stranger," and l-pei means "strangers." The English lan- guage gives analogous illustrations in \vords like "mankind," " Christendom." 58 THE LOGIC OF NAMES. definition of a name as the distinctive mark of one sensation, or one group of sensations. 60. It may be remarked that Q admits indif- ferently of the values 1 and 0. Therefore it would be admissible as the expression of the numerical value of a logical name, and would imply that that name was of indefinite numerical value. Such a name is "animal," in "All men are animals," for its numerical value is determined by that of the other term, and may, therefore, be either 1 or 0. Relatively to its original numerical value, absolute 1. it may now be any fraction of 1 ; yet whatever fraction it may be relatively and in form, that fraction must be absolutely equal to either 1 or 0 ; a condition satisfied by the fraction g. g in this use finds an expression in the name " some," and " men are some animals " is accord- ingly a correct paraphrase of " men are animals." XXI. CLASSIFICATION. — Coleridge asked his son why he was called Hartley. " Which Hartley? " said the boy. " Why, is there more than one Hartley ? " " Yes, there is a deal of Hartleys ; there is picture Hartley" (Hazlitt had painted a picture of him), " and Shadow Hartley, and there 's Echo Hartley, and there 's Catch-me-fast Hartley," "seizing his own arm very eagerly. Hartley perhaps thought that for every separate word used as a name there must exist in nature a separate thing, and that the same thing has no business to have more than one name. We may CLASSIFICATION. 59 suppose him to have gone on from this beginning to discover that there were more " picture people " in the world than himself, and that in the various simple names he had been putting together to form names of himself, all but the one word Hartley were common names. This discovery would have introduced him to the science of Classification. 62. Picture, Shadow, Echo and Catch-me-fast, are all names which, in the sense given them by Hartley, are each respectively common to more than one person or thing, and they in conse- quence require the addition of the word "Hartley " to make them proper names. By themselves, in Hartley's use of them, and as numerical symbols, they each have a numerical value greater than 1, the numerical value of the name Hartley is neither more nor less than 1. 63. We may also conceive Hartley to have ex- tended his list, and to have consequently found words of a sort such that, while they are common to respectively different numbers of things, they are all, for a certain number, common to the same things. A series of this kind would be, for one — pictures, artificial-representations, works of man, productions generally ; for another — echo, sound, vibration, motion ; for a third — philosopher, man, animal. Philosopher and man are, up to a certain number, common to the same things ; but, assum- ing that philosophy is confined to man, the numerical value of man is greater than that of philosopher ; it is a common name to more things than philosopher is common to ; there are some 60 THE LOGIC OF NAMES. men who are not philosophers, though all philoso- phers are men. In the same manner, and on the same supposition, the numerical value of animals is in such a way greater than those of men and of philosophers, that all philosophers are men, all men are animals, while some animals are neither men nor philosophers ; others are men but not philosophers ; others, again, all the rest in fact, are both men and philosophers. Hartley, philoso- pher, man, animal, then, form a series in which every subsequent includes, numerically and identi- cally, its antecessor ; the numerical value increasing at every remove from the initial name, which, its numerical value being 1, we may call the unit term. The end of such a series, (and every possible name can be placed in such a series), may be nothing but the boundary, in that direc- tion, of language itself.* After animal might come living-body, with a still greater numerical value than animal, but yet inclusive of it. In the same way, after living-body might come body. In the language of common logic the denotation, or extension, of the names in the series * " Thus proceeding, and at each step ejecting from the com- prehension those chanicters which are found the proximate im- pediments to the amplification of the extension of the concept, we at each step diminish the former quantity precisely as we in- crease the latter ; till, at last, we arrive at that concept which is the necessary constituent of every other, — as that concept which all comprehension and all extension must equally contain, hut in which comprehension is at its minimum, extension at its maxi- mum,— I mean the concept of Being or Existence." — Sir W. Hamilton. CLASSIFICATION. 61 regularly increases as we proceed from the unit term. 64. Again, another fact to be noticed about the series in question is, that philosopher is not really the name of all Hartley, but only of what in Hartley is common to him and other philoso- phers. Man, similarly, is not the name of all philosopher, but only of what is common to philosopher with man who is not philosopher, of the human body with its living, sentient and reasoning forces. And so on, as we proceed in the series, we have to drop one part of the mean- ing of the initial name, Hartley, after another part, until we have nothing but body left, out of Hartley, as that for which the last member of the series is the actual name. To revert to the dis- tinction of a previous paragraph, the last name of the series is that of the simplest thing, the first of the most complex ; the last stands for the minimum number of grouped sensations, the first for the maximum number; and exactly in accordance with their respective places in their series, will the intervening names differ in the same relation. The meaning of each term in a series is thus less than and included in the term that precedes, greater than and inclusive of the term that follows. It is with special reference to this re- lation, the opposite relation to that of extension or denotation, that logicians call the meaning of a term its intension, comprehension or connotation. 65. To form such a series as the one we have been considering is differently called abstraction 62 THE LOGIC OF NAMES. or determination. It is called abstraction when, to make it, we proceed from the initial or unit term by taking away from the meaning of each name successively in order to get at the next name. When we proceed in the contrary direction, that is to say from the term of maximum numerical value, we return to each preceding name by cutting off so much of the numerical value of its successor, and the process is called determination. 66. The things to which any one name is common, form by that fact a class.* The series we have been considering may therefore be called a scheme of classification. In such schemes, the unit term — that is, the term which has unity for its numerical value — may be dis- tinguished as the name of the individual.^ The other names are class names ; and of the class names, that which comes next after the individual is the name of the infima species, so called, because, according to the scheme, it contains individuals only and not classes. All the other species de- noted by the other class names, do contain classes. The species named next after the infima species, in the present case, obviously contains two classes or species, namely, the infima species or philoso- * The technical terms of logic, such as genus, species, etc., are called in the literature of logic, names of the second intention. The name of anything viewed as a mere existence, such as desk, table, etc., is a name of the first intention. f So called because its numerical value 1 is not divisible in logic ; logical division being the resolution into its parts of the extension of a name. CLASSIFICATION. 63 pher, and the class which we may nominate non- philosopher. Relatively to these two contained species, it itself is styled a genus ; but relatively to its succeeding term, " animal," it is a species ; and " animal " to it is a genus. The class " animal," again, contains at least two species, man and not-man. To them it is a genus, and in turn is itself a species to the succeeding term. This double character will be found to attach to every term in succession between the name of the infima species and the last term. As the series stands, Body, obviously can be a genus alone, and not a species. It is, therefore, distinguished as the summum genus ; the other genera being called subalterna genera. 67. The series which has just been analysed is a typical series. Nearly every name, simple or compound, may be made the unit term of an indefinite number of such series. Every com- pound name may, in like manner, be made the summum genus of more or fewer such series, converging to it as to a common centre. Thus, a compound name may be the meeting point for an indefinite number of other series, each starting from an independent unit term. For example, Hartley. Boxer. Philosopher. Mastiff. Oaks. Palms. I III Man. Dog. Exogens. Endcgens. Animals. Plants. -^, Living Bodies. 64 THE LOGIC OF NAMES. 68. Here "man" and "dog" are both species, co-ordinate specie*, of the including genus next after them, their proximate genus,* as it is called, namely, animals; "animal" and "plant," again, are co-ordinate to each other, and their proximate genus is " living body." That which distinguishes a species from its co-ordinates is called its dif- ferentia. 69. Classification, though a very important part of most works on logic, is not a part of logic. It is a separate branch of knowledge, a distinct science. The distinction, however, has not been recognised, and classification is so conveniently treated with logic, that the meaning of the name logic is most frequently wrested into an inclusion of classification as a part of logic. But classifi- cation plainly has to do with the matter of thought, as opposed to the form. Those, consequently, who limit logic to being a science of the forms of thought, ought to exclude classification^ Classi- * The genus next above any given species is called proximate. f The following description of classification occurs in Arch- bishop Thomson's " Applied Logic," and is interesting, not only in itself, but as illustrating the extra logical character of classifica- tion:— "A class cannot always be defined in words, so as to de- scribe every species in it. From the lowest of its subdivisions to the highest, we pass through so many shades of difference, that we have a difficulty in perceiving and expressing the likeness between the extremes ; and properties which were prominent at the bottom of the scale, are in the higher steps forgotten, as nobler ones come into view. To distinguish the polyp, the lowest species in the animal series, from a plant, it imist be defined as ' having a digestive cavity' ; whereas, the definition usually given for higher animals, and for the conception animal in general, con- CLASSIFICATION. 65 fication, again, implies that a name can have numerical values other than 1 or 0. It, there- fore, stands outside the method of this logic, where no name, as a name, can have any other numerical value than 1 or 0. Classification, ac- cordingly, is a separate science, as the science of names considered both as names and as symbols veys that they are ' heings endowed with life and sensation.' Still •we group them together by our perception of likeness ; which, though not so obviously applicable to the ends of the series viewed together, and apart from the intermediate links, become so when we pass regularly along the chain. We might not be able to prove that the polyp had sensation at all, if there were not creatures a little higher in the scale of being, resembling the polyp in other particulars, and exhibiting more plainly the sense of feeling. "We presume that it exists in the lower, be- cause we see it in the higher, and though it decreases as we de- scend, we cannot show that it has ceased. The definition of a genus is the adequate definition of its lowest species only, since one which included any higher properties than the lowest ex- hibits, would of course exclude it. But in classification, the definition is not so much used as the type, by likeness or un- likeness to which we arrange the others, and assign them a higher or lower degree. " Though the species in any great class rise by the steps of a regular arrangement, the same series must not be continued from the highest of one kingdom to the lowest of the next above it. The highest plant is often considered next below the lowest animal, whereas it is much more like, though infinitely inferior to, the highest animal. The animal, vegetable, and mineral king- doms rather resemble ladders of equal height resting upon three different steps of a house, than ladders raised one upon the other. The lowest animal, the lowest plant, and the lowest mineral answer to each other ; and the complex animal organism, the tall and beautiful tree, and the regular group of crystals, corre- spond in some measure at the top of the respective scales." — ARCHBISHOP Thomson, pp. 264, 5. F 66 THE LOGIC OF NAMES. of number. In this view, classification is an im- portant though not an extensive branch of know- ledge. And it is necessary, as a part of education which the logician may naturally take within his charge, generally to understand the nomenclature which classification has introduced into litera- ture. 70. The leading fact in the science of classifi- cation, is the distinction of names into connotative and denotative. By the connotative import of a name we signify its meaning, the attributes it implies or connotes ; by its denotative import we signify the individuals, or classes of individuals, which possess those connoted attributes. If we consider the schemes of classification into which the names of our sensations arrange themselves, we shall perceive that in many the connotation or meaning of class names is indefinite. A sensation on each new repetition, resolves itself into new elements, and human experience, in many cases, has not yet completed this process of resolution. Thus it happens that, with our means, it is as yet impossible to exhaust the meanings or connotations of such names as man, sheep, etc. At the same time, the meaning or connotation of quadrangle, or triangle, is very definite. This distinction between definite and indefinite meanings is recog- nised in the science of classification. That part of the meaning or connotation of a class-name which constitutes its proximate genus, and serves to distinguish it as a species from its co-ordinate species, is called its essence. If, for example, animal CLASSIFICATION. 67 is a proximate genus to the species man, if the possession of reason distinguishes the species man from the other constituents of animal, then " ra- tional animal " expresses the essence of man. The essence of a class name, therefore, consists of two parts : that which expresses its proximate genus, and is called the genus, in the case just cited, "animal" ; and that which distinguishes it from its co-classes, from its co-ordinate species, and is called its differentia. What of the connotation or meaning of a class name is not included in its essence, constitutes its propria. A proprium may be defined as one of those attributes of a name or thing which do not enter into its essence. The name proprium simply means, proper to, and should, therefore, signify all those simple sensa- tions which the resolution of a compound sensa- tion into its elements may be made constantly to exhibit. As a consequence, those names which mark the genus and differentia are also propria, and propria may be divided into 1st. Those which express the genus of the name into the meaning of which they enter. 2nd. Those which distinguish the species. 3rd. Those which, constituting neither the genus nor the differentia, still always appear in the analysis of the meaning. 71. The analysis of a compound sensation will, however, generally yield elements which, or the names of which, cannot be considered propria, inasmuch as they are not found to be present in all analyses. In a number of successive repe- 68 THE LOGIC OF NAMES. titions of the sensation "horse," for instance, we may observe sometimes that the element "black" appears among the rest, at other times "white," sometimes both, and so on. Black, white, etc., are, therefore, not proper but possible 'elements in the exhibitions of the compound sensation Horse. Classification calls them accidents.* 72. The immediate application of the theory of classification is to Definition, or the resolution into its parts of the comprehension of a name, and to Division, or the like resolution of the extension of a name. 73. Division is part of Determination, in that it descends from genus to species ; but its peculiar office is to divide the proximate genera of a com- pound series of class names into their constituent species. This process of division is partly arbi- trary, and partly fixed. It is arbitrary, because the same name may appear as proximate genus to more than one system of constituent species. For instance, Star may be a star which revolves only round its own centre, i.e., a star fixed ; or a star * A distinction is sometimes made between separable accidents and inseparable; tbose accidents which, experience tells us are practically universal of the name, although no part, and in no visible relation to any part, of its meaning, being called in- separable. . Black is thus an inseparable accident of crow, though we may conceive a white crow ; and although if we saw a bird in all respects like a crow, but white, and not black in colour, we should call it a crow. In the language of Archbishop Thomson, " accident is a quality which belongs indeed to a subject, but can be taken away from it without destroying its nature or essence." CLASSIFICATION. 69 which revolves round a fixed star ; or a star which revolves round a star that itself moves round another star ; or a star which revolves round a point in space external to it. Or again, Star may be a star with rings and moons ; with rings but not moons ; with moons but not rings ; or with neither rings nor moons. 74. In division, then, the selection of the prin- ciple of division, the fundamentum relationis, as it is called, is more or less arbitrary. We have seen that, in dividing " Star," the principle of division may be either Position relative to a centre of revolution, or Concomitancy of certain adjuncts. And it would have been possible to select other relations as principles of division, for many others would be suggested by observation. It is in applying the arbitrarily selected principle that division becomes fixed. The principle, once chosen, must be adhered to throughout the process. It would not be a just division to divide stars into stars fixed, stars revolving round other stars, and stars with satellites ; for, to speak of nothing else, in such a division more than one Jundamentum relationis would have been made use of. 75. Another condition of division is, that the numerical value of the constituent species must be together equal to that of the proximate genus. Practically, this rule is applied by asking whether there is in the genus any individual to be found which is not to be found in any one of the con- stituent species ; and by applying a third rule, 70 THE LOGIC OF NAMES. which lays down that no one individual must be found in more than one species of the same division. A fourth rule, the completing condition of a just division, is, that every individual in the species must also belong to the genus. For that process of division, however, which is regarded as most purely logical, the first only of these rules is required as a guide, the others are only useful as tests. This process is known as Dichotomy, which means division into pairs of opposites. By "opposites" we signify the opposition between the members of a pair, like Policemen, and not- policemen. The second member of this pair may be again divided into a similar pair, as People imprisoned, and people not-imprisoned. It is evident that such a process might be carried on to an indefinite extent. 76. As division is a particular operation in de- termination, so definition is included in abstraction. The rules for performing it having been already sufficiently illustrated, it is enough here to simply state them. The definition of a name should give the essence of the name ; nothing beyond the essence, and nothing short of the essence. The definition of philosopher, for example, should show that a philosopher must be a man ; it should contain enough to distinguish philosopher from all non-philosophers, but it should not con- tain more than this. 77. It is obvious that a logic, which limits numerical values to 1 or 0, recognises definitions, but not divisions. LOGICAL ADDITION. 71 XXII. LOGICAL ADDITION. — The schemes of classification treated of in the preceding section, though they come within the plan of this book, diverge from its method, which, as said before, knows no numerical value of a name save 1 or 0, and, consequently, takes no account of what is called in grammar, plurality ; in logic, extension or denotation. It considers a proximate genus as a physical whole — a group of sensations, and its division into the constituent species, therefore, as an act of what, as division, is technically styled partition.* In other words, it reduces logical division to definition. Nevertheless, it finds an expression for the relation of co-ordinate species to one another ; thus — A. mastiff is an animal. A man is an animal. A mastiff and a man are animals. 79. These three propositions are all indepen- dently intelligible and demonstrable, while the third can be made out from the first and second by the process of logical addition, of which "and," * Partition in logic is generally defined to be the division of the individual — of the unit term, in a scheme of classification. According to the logical theory which calls the unit term indi- vidual, this is impossible, and partition, therefore, is reckoned extra-logical. Logical division, by the same reasoning, and also because it is confined to the analysis of extension, is only appli- cable to class names. The division of an arrow into the point, the shaft, and the feather is intended for an act of partition ; but the division of missiles into those which are propelled by me- chanical forces, and those which are propelled by chemical forces, is intended for an act of logical partition. 72 THE LOGIC OF NAMES. and the plural sign are symbols. " And," it may be remarked, which here is a sign of logical addition, sometimes betokens logical multiplica- tion ; as in " Ammonia has-a-pungent-smell, and exercises-a- powerful-corrosive- action - on - animal- tissues." 80. Logical addition may be defined as the ex- pression of a partition of a logical whole. XXIII. LOGICAL SUBTRACTION.— As one group of sensations may be contained in another group, the expression of its withdrawal from the con- taining group would be a name for the sensations left after its withdrawal, and would be the ex- pression of an operation which may be conve- niently styled logical subtraction. The operation so indicated may be impossible in fact, or may be only indicated and not performed. Indeed, the logic of names can in no case have to do with the performance. 82. As an example of the expression in lan- guage of logical subtraction, we may instance non-philosopher. This is, in effect, the expression of the subtraction of "philosopher" from some group of sensations which includes philosopher, and is, therefore, a name for the remainder which such an operation, if performed, would leave. The including class is generally taken for the proximate genus which, in the case of philo- sopher, is man. 83. All negative names may be subjected to the same analysis as non-philosopher. Any group LOGICAL SUBTRACTION. 73 of sensations, in fact, may be imagined to be subtracted from an including group of sensations, even though all we know about such an: including group is, that if it existed and had a name, the numerical value of that name would certainly be 1. Thus it has been possible for common lan- guage to contain such a word as nothing. Tiling is a name of that universal logical relation which binds up all our sensations into one logical whole. It stands for the whole of our knowledge, and its subtraction from something greater than itself is, therefore, both a numerical and logical impossi- bility. Not/ting, consequently, is an uninter- pretable symbol, and is used in logic much as -s/ — 1 is used in Trigonometry. The same mode of interpretation will explain Infinite. 84. It follows, unity being the most general representative we can have of the name of the including group of sensations, from which we are supposed to take the group signified by the given positive name, that, if any positive name be given, the corresponding negative name may be signified by the expression of the logical subtrac- tion of the positive name from unity. Such an expression, be it noted, is not in itself a name, but used for a name — for the name which the remainder has, may have, or might have. A negative name is, therefore, a true pronoun. 85. Finally, it should be clearly understood that the operation of logical subtraction, as indicated in a negative name, is only indicated but not performed. To actually take one name from 74 THE LOGIC OF NAMES. another name is impossible ; to actually take the numerical value of one name from that of another, both names being assumed to be names of realities, will leave nothing as a remainder. 86. It is perhaps, therefore, incorrect to say that a negative, (or privative) name is the opposite of its positive. In the first place, we have seen that it is not absolutely but only provisionally a name ; it is an expression for a name. In the second place, looking at the components of the expression, a negative name, if a name, is a name which is not a name ; and a privative name in the same way is a name, if a name, which is deprived of all meaning. The negative names in language may be divided into two classes : first, those which indicate the operation of logical subtraction, such as those we have been considering ; second, those that are in reality positive names, as "unmer- ciful," which practically means " cruel." To this latter class Archbishop Thomson's instance of a privative conception, unkindness, would seem to belong. XXIY. PREDICATION.— In any proposition, that term which determines for common language the numerical value of the other term, is called the subject * of that proposition. In Men are animals, Some men are animals, * Subject, in the logical sense of the word, is by Hobbes made equivalent 1o supposition, or hypnkeimeuon. But it more natu- rally may be derived from its philosophical antithesis to object. PREDICATIOX. 75 "Men" and "Some men" are the subjects of their respective propositions. In each proposition " animals " has a particular numerical value, de- rived from its place in that proposition, and different from what it would have if itself were the subject of a proposition. The term which thus has its numerical value determined for it is called the predicate of the proposition.* Object may mean, first, that which absolutely is, whether known to exist or not ; or, second, that which is only supposed to exist, and exists relatively only, that is, exists relatively to the knower. John Smith has an absolute existence as an individual man ; as a father he has a relative existence, he exists relatively to John Smith, his son. Taking any object, that which is in it is sub- jective with regard to that object ; that which is external to it is objective. Taking the mind as an object, an act of imagination is subjective to the mind ; an image of imagination is objective. Taking a horse as an object, the horse, as existing, is subjective ; as known to a man, the horse is objective. Thus, everything is capable both of an objective and subjective relation. And thus, as everything knows or is known, everything subjectively knows or is objectively known. Taking any individual man, to him his conscious mind, or ego, knows, and all other things are known. That, therefore, which resides in, belongs to, or is dependent on the knowing mind in general, may be generally called subject, or subjective; everything not falling under this head, which does not reside in, belong to, or depend upon the knowing mind, will be object, or objective. And by an obvious analogy, on the one hand, men have given the name subject to that term of a propo- sition which determines numerical value for the other term, finally ending by construing subject into a synonym of object ; on the other hand, they have made object a synonym of motive end, final cause. — From SIR William Hamilton, in his edition of Reid, * With respect to such a proposition as " No men are perfect," in this connection, the reader is referred to the section headed " Negative Propositions." 76 THE LOGIC OF NAMES. 88. Generally speaking, a name may be said to be a predicate of any name into the meaning of which, it enters, or with which it enters, by mul- tiplication, into the meaning of another name. In its relation to any one or more of its pre- dicates, again, any name may be called a subject. In a proposition, however, viewed as a logical equation, there can be admitted no such difference between the terms as is implied by the distinction of subject and predicate. But when a proposition is viewed as a sentence, the distinction becomes useful to the grammarian.* 89. We may avail ourselves of the distinction in propositions between subject and predicate, and of the distinction in terms between distributed and undistributed, to shortly state the common logical division of propositions into universal and particular. Those propositions are universal which have the subject distributed; those are particular which have the subject undistributed. Thus, " Men are animals," is a universal propo- sition ; " Some men are animals," is a particular proposition. * Of the relations between -words which are named by gram- marians, that designated by the word " predication " seems the only one which can be called a relation of thought. It is a per- fectly universal relation. Thus, an article or a preposition is the pronominal name of a relation as predicated of a noun ; an ad- jective or adverb is the name of a quality as predicated of a noun or verb; a conjunction, when used to connect sentences, is the name of a proposition as predicated of another proposition. And if the logical copula is taken to be anything more than a sign of predication, it must be taken as predicated of the subject, and the following noun or adjective as predicated of the copula. PREDICABLES. 77 XXY. PREDICABLES. — Any two names which may form the two terms of the same proposition are predicable one of the other. An adjective, consequently, ought to be predicable of its sub- stantive. 91. It is a consequence of the numerical equality which is a property of logical equality that the terms of a proposition are mutually pre- dicable. But as common language exclusively determines the numerical value of the predicate by that of the subject, not by a distinct expres- sion, the terms of a proposition of common lan- guage, taken literally, cannot always be said to be mutually predicable, the subject cannot be in its turn always literally predicable of the predi- cate. In technical phrase, a proposition of common language is not always simply convertible, in fact, is never convertible, except when the terms are both distributed or both undistributed. 92. The same defect of common language pre- vents an adjective and its substantive from being mutually predicable. In common language, an adjective, as a numerical symbol, stands for more things than its substantive stands for. Its exten- sion is greater. But the numerical value or ex- tension of the predicate must be equal to, or greater than, that of the subject. 93. In the literature of logic, a predicable is a word that can be used as a predicate. There are five classes or two classes of such words. The five classes are an inference from the typical scheme of classification. "With respect to any 78 THE LOGIC OF NAMES. two names which occur in a scheme of classifica- tion, and which are taken as the subject and pre- dicate, respectively, of a proposition, the predi- cate must express either the genus, the difference, or the species ; a property or an accident. Ac- cording to the more reasonable division into two classes, a predicate may express either the whole meaning of a name, or part only of the meaning. In the former case it is a definition, in the latter an attribute. XXYI. LOGICAL MULTIPLICATION. — It has been already provided that the mutual predication of names that are written together, so as to repre- sent the compound name of one logical whole, may be distinguished as logical multiplication, The verbal exhibitions of logical multiplication and some consequences which come from it may be here conveniently illustrated. 95. In "this hat is black," this and hat are logically multiplied together. In " this is a black hat "black and hat are logically multiplied together. Generally, therefore, the names which form any compound name, and which, consequently, are all compredicable of the same thing, are to be con- sidered as logically multiplied together. When now a compound name is the name of a non- existent— 'that is, when the names composing it are the names of sensations that cannot come together, are non-compredicable names — the numerical value of that compound must be, as we have seen in a preceding paragraph, equal to 0. That is to LOGICAL MULTIPLICATION. 79 say, the result of the multiplication together of the factors composing that compound name is 0, and the predication or predications which it im- plies are false. 96. The following examples, of which the third is, by logical multiplication, a deduction from the others, may now be intelligible* : — i. Man is mortal. II. Man is immortal, in. Man man is mortal immortal. 97. The subjects of i. and 11. multiplied to- gether are unchanged. A name multiplied by itself equals itself. The square of a name equals the name.f The subject of in. might be as well expressed by " man " as by " man man." And this is reasonable. For names stand for sensa- tions. But a sensation repeated is the same sensa- tion still. 98. Again, supposing mortal to be the pure negative of immortal, the two words multiplied together must equal nothing. For, together, * It may be rendered more intelligible by the following ex- ample : — i. Honesty is deserving reward, ii. A negro is a fellow-creature. in. An honest negro is a fellow-creature deserving reward. The two logical equations, I. and II., logically multiplied to- gether, produce III. The example is taken from Archbishop Thomson, who brings it forward as an instance of " Immediate Inference by added Determinants." t In mathematical language, if x stand for the name of any logical whole, then, x*=x. The same follows, also, from the numerical value of a name as the sign of a logical whole. Either i, o, or ?, multiplied into itself, equals itself. 80 THE LOGIC OF NAMES. they form the compound name of a plain non- existent ; one of them is a false predication. Again, taken separately, both being predicated of the same subject in i. and u. ; one must of necessity be a true predication, and the other a false one. Then the numerical value of the one, will be 1, of the other, 0. But these numbers multiplied together as numbers equal 0 ; just as we have seen that the corresponding names when multiplied together are equal to 0. Hence we may take as a rule, that a name logically multi- plied into its negative must give 0 as the numerical value of the resulting compound name.* XXVII. NEGATIVE PROPOSITIONS.— The inter- pretation given above of negative names applies equally to negative propositions. A proposition is but a name in analysis or synthesis, and a nega- tive attached to it which is to be referred not to the subject nor to the predicate, but to the whole proposition, merely indicates that the compound sensation signified by the proposition is to be considered as subtracted from a larger and in- cluding sensation. The operation itself, it may be remarked, is signified by the negative sign only, which in effect declares that the name or proposition to which it is attached, is the subject of the operation. In a negative name, then, the * Numerically, this rule is deducible from the law xI=x, an equation which may be written thus, x — 0^=0, whence x(i — x)=0. It is obvious that the rule, whether stated in words or in symbols, is only an expression of the principle of contradiction. NEGATIVE PROPOSITIONS. 81 negative sign plays the part of an adjective, in a negative proposition, of a predicate. A nega- tive proposition is not a simple but a compound proposition. It is a proposition which for a subject has another proposition. 100. This analysis of negative propositions is to some extent verified by the forms of language. In English, the universal negative proposition is idiomatically expressed thus — JVo men are good, where the negative is placed before the proposi- tion as an adjective before its substantive, and, accordantly with the genius of the language, can be referred neither to subject, copula, nor pre- dicate.* 101. In view of this interpretation f of-a nega- tive proposition, it becomes useless to dispute whether the negative proposition should be attached to the predicate or the copula. If to enunciate a negative proposition is to affirm a negative of an affirmative proposition taken as a subject, the negative proposition is only a com- plex form of the affirmative proposition. 102. In ordinary logic, the recognition of the * So, in the common example, " All that glitters is not gold," what is meant is, "it is not true that all that glitters is gold." Those who virtually take " not " as part of the predicate are obliged to apply a collective in place of a distributive sense to " all." t Countenanced, I observe, by the high authority of Mr. Latham, who " doubts whether it be in accordance with the phe- nomena of language to make the negative element of propositions a part of either predicate or copula." — Logic, p. 26. 82 THE LOGIC OF NAMES. negative form of proposition doubles the number of types. As there is an affirmative universal, so there must be a negative universal ; and with the affirmative particular also must stand the negative particular.* All negative propositions distribute the predicate. If we say " no men are innocent," we assert of all innocent things that none of them are men. If we say " some triangles are not scalene," we assert of all scalene triangles that they number none of those particular triangles that we define by the word " some." 103. Affirmative propositions, on the contrary, do not distribute the predicate. When we say " All men are animals," or " Some men are animals," we do not speak of all animals. 104. Finally, as the subject of every universal proposition is distributed (see the section headed Predication), and the subject of every particular proposition undistributed, it follows that the uni- versal affirmative has the subject alone distributed, the universal negative both subject and predicate, the particular negative only the predicate, the particular affirmative neither subject nor predi- cate. XXVIII. THE CALCULUS OF LOGIC. — "We have seen that the logic of names provides for the ex- pression of operations on names and of the uni- * The attribution to a proposition of affirmation or negation constitutes its quality; of universality or particularity, its quantity. THE CALCULUS OF LOGIC. 83 versal logical relation between names, of logical multiplication, addition, subtraction, and of logical equality : that we may indicate operations on names that neither are nor can be performed ; and that in all operations and equalities the names employed must each have for its numerical value either 1 or 0. These facts constitute the basis of Professor Boole's " Calculus of Logic," which may be denned to consist of the laws, the axioms, and the processes of an Algebra, in which the symbols x, y, .?, etc., admit indifferently of the values 0 and 1, and of these values alone. APPENDIX. Mr. Stanley Jevons has published a work entitled "Pure Logic," which he, himself, characterises as being little more than an attempt to translate Professor Boole's forms into processes of self-evident meaning and force. The mention of this fact may introduce certain observations that have been suggested by Mr. Jevons' s critical remarks on Professor Boole's system, — re- marks which the present writer is the more induced to notice, because they constitute the only detailed criticism of Professor Boole's system which he has been yet fortunate enough to meet with. Mr. Jevons1 s remarks are chiefly grouped under separate " ob- jections." His first objection is that " Boole's symbols are essen- tially different from the names or symbols of common discourse, — his logic is not the logic of common thought." Mr. Jevons, in enforcing this objection, remarks that Professor Boole's symbols, in expressing this proposition, " A peer is either a duke, or a marquis, or an earl, or a viscount, or a baron," would necessarily imply that a peer can not be at once a duke and marquis, or marquis and earl. The answer is, that while common discourse can, but does not, express the compredicability of these various titles, it is a cardinal point with Professor Boole, equally with Sir William Hamilton, that everything implied in thought should be expressed by Logic. He would, therefore, before symbolising the given sentence, enquire whether the terms " duke," " marquis," etc., were meant to be mutually exclusive or not : it is therefore not strictly correct to say that his symbols, if expressing the given sentence, would necessarily imply that a duke could not be a marquis. Mr. Jevons, indeed, seems to think that such a preliminary enquiry is " consulting the matter," and therefore extra-logical. But until it is known what meaning he attaches, in this connection, to the phrase "consulting the matter," it is only necessary to say, that Professor Boole's logic is scientific ; common discourse is unscientific, and leaves things to be understood which science expresses. But as the logic only pretends to interpret the dis- course, this difference between them seems hardly to constitute an essential difference. At any rate, Mr. Jevons's objection is APPENDIX. 85 equally valid against Professor Boole's symbol for A, y=vx, against Sir William Hamilton's "all x is some y" and against, perhaps, the majority of logicians, who, if they do not name the some in A, direct the student to think it. Mr. Jevons again takes the form #= y + z, and then calls x " Caesar"; y, " Conqueror of the Gauls" ; z, " First Emperor of Home"; from these assignments, interpreting the form to mean " Caesar is the conqueror of the Gauls or the first emperor of Eome." Next he proceeds to subtract z from both sides, getting x—z=y, and thus, with some triumph, interprets the result, "Caesar, providing he is not the first emperor of Rome, is the conqueror of the Gauls ! " It is perhaps sufficient to say here that Mr. Jevons treats Pro- fessor Boole's symbols as he would not treat those of common algebra. It would be easy, by assigning arbitrary values to the separate symbols involved in a given equation, to deduce all manner of absurd consequences from their connection as fixed by the equation. "Were the sentence " Caesar is the conqueror of the Gauls or the first emperor of Rome," submitted in good faith to Professor Boole's system, the first question would be what " or " meant. Is it disjunctive, as in " saint or sinner," and in "saint or latter-day saint," or is it expressive of a synonym, as in " sleep or slumber"? If the former, the symbolical expression of the sentence " Caesar is the conqueror of the Gauls or the first emperor of Rome " might be something like the form given by Mr. Jevons, as x=y (1 — z)+(l — y] z; or x=y -f (1 — y) z; if the latter, x=yz. In common discourse the same questions would have to be somehow answered before the meaning of the proposition could be considered to be settled. In this case again we find common discourse to be ambiguous, so far unscientific, and so far necessarily different from what logic necessarily must be, so long as logic pretends to be a science. The second objection, which is that there are no such opera- tions in pure logic as addition and subtraction, may be taken with the third, which is that Professor Boole's system is "inconsistent with the self-evident law of thought" in Mr. Stanley Jevons' s system, a law which he expresses thus, (A +A=A). It is perplexing to find Mr. Jevons first stating that there is no such thing in his logic as addition, and then, in almost the next page, using the sign of addition in enunciating his own 86 APPENDIX. " self-evident law of thought." It can only he conjectured that one of two things is the case, — either that Mr. Jevons uses the sign of addition where Professor Boole uses that of multiplication, or that he has omitted to take into account the import of the first proposition in Professor Boole's chapter of "Abbreviations." It may be admitted, however, that Professor Boole's phraseology does not always recognise the distinction between the logics of extension and intension. The fourth and last objection taken against Professor Boole's system, is taken d-propos of the symbols I, 9, ", -. Shortly stated, it is that the calculus made use of by Professor Boole is a system which only points out truths that, by another system of reasoning, we have to learn are certainly true. This objection, if subjected to certain modifications, has a justification. It need only be added here now, that whatever agreements or disagreements may exist between their views on matters of detail, the present writer cordially concurs with Mr. Jevons where the latter says of logic as it now is, since the appearance of Professor Boole's "Laws of Thought," that it "is to logic before that work as mathematics with equations of any degree are to mathematics with equations of only one degree." INDEX. *#* The Figures refer to paragraphs. A, 25. Abstraction, 14, 15, 18, 34, 65, 76. Accidents, 71. Affirmative propositions, 103. Attributes, 42, 93. Axiom, 48. Categories, 38. Class, 66. Classification, 54, 61. Cognition (symbolical), 37. Class-name, 17, 66. Common names, 57. Comparison, 14, 15. Comprehension, 42, 64. Concept, 11, 14, 15, 17, 48. Conception (relative), 46. Concrete, 34. Connotation, 42, 64. Connotative, 70. Consciousness, 20, 21. Contradiction, 21, 98. Convertible, 91. Co-ordinate species, 68. Copula, 49. Corollary, 48. Data, 48. Declaration, 43. Definition, 43, 72, 76, 93. Denomination, 15. Demonstration, 48. Denotation, 63, 64. Denotative, 70. Description, 43, 44. Determination, 63. Dichotomy, 75. Difference, 21. Differentia, 68, 70. Distribution, 59, 102. Division, 73. Equal, 16. Equivocal, 28. Essence, 70. Explication, 43. Exposition, 43.. Extension, 63, 64. Fallacies, 36. Generalization, 15. Genus, 66. Grammar, 22. Hypothesis, 48. Idea, 11, 17. Idea, innate, 14. Identical, 16. Identity, 16. Identity, the principle of, 21. Interrogative, 31. Individual, 66. Infima species, 66. Intension, 42, 64. Intention (first and second), 66. Judgment, 48. Knowledge, 47- Language, 7, 22. Lemma, 48. Like, 16. Logic, 1, 2. Logical addition, 53, 78, 80. Logical equality, 55. Logical multiplication, 25, 52, 79, 94. Logical subtraction, 81. Logical whole, 25, 51, 80. Meaning, 39. Memory, 14. Metaphorical, 28. Metaphysics, 14. INDEX. Middle, law of excluded, 21. Mind, 2. Names, 24, 37, 40, 51. Naming, 7, 8. Negative propositions, 99, 102. Negative words, 33, 83, 98, 99. Nervous action, 4. Nothing, 83. Notion, 11, 14, 17. Number, 25. Numerical value, 57. Particular, 89. Partition, 78. Parts of speech, 25. Perception, 11, 14, 15, 17. Postulate, 48. Predicables, 90. Predicate, 87. Predication, 87. Privative names, 86. Problem, 48. Pronominal words, 28, 34, 36. Proper names, 57. Propositions, 14, 48, 50. Proprium, 70. Proximate genus, 68. Psychology, 2. Quaestio, 48. Quality, 102. Quantity, 102. Reflection, 15. Eelation, 34, 46, 50, 55. Relative conceptions, 46. Representations, 14. Resemblance, 16. Scholion, 48. Sensations, 8, 9. Sensations, compound, 11. Solution, 48. Some, 25. Species, 66. Subaltema genera, 66. Subject, 87. Summum genus, 66. Symbolical cognition, 37. Terms, 50. The, 25. Thesis, 48. Thought, 3. Universal, 89. Univocal, 28. Words, 23. University of California SOUTHERN REGIONAL LIBRARY FACILITY Return this material to the library from which it was borrowed. OCT 1 1 1989 OCT24 DUE Recall ECEIVED OCT 0 8 SRLF QUARTER